Menu
Home Explore People Places Arts History Plants & Animals Science Life & Culture Technology
On this page
Gödel operation

In mathematical set theory, a set of Gödel operations is a finite collection of operations on sets that can be used to construct the constructible sets from ordinals. Gödel (1940) introduced the original set of 8 Gödel operations 𝔉1,...,𝔉8 under the name fundamental operations. Other authors sometimes use a slightly different set of about 8 to 10 operations, usually denoted G1, G2,...

We don't have any images related to Gödel operation yet.
We don't have any YouTube videos related to Gödel operation yet.
We don't have any PDF documents related to Gödel operation yet.
We don't have any Books related to Gödel operation yet.
We don't have any archived web articles related to Gödel operation yet.

Definition

Gödel (1940) used the following eight operations as a set of Gödel operations (which he called fundamental operations):

  1. F 1 ( X , Y ) = { X , Y } {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {F}}_{1}(X,Y)=\{X,Y\}}
  2. F 2 ( X , Y ) = E ⋅ X = { ( a , b ) ∈ X ∣ a ∈ b } {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {F}}_{2}(X,Y)=E\cdot X=\{(a,b)\in X\mid a\in b\}}
  3. F 3 ( X , Y ) = X − Y {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {F}}_{3}(X,Y)=X-Y}
  4. F 4 ( X , Y ) = X ↾ Y = X ⋅ ( V × Y ) = { ( a , b ) ∈ X ∣ b ∈ Y } {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {F}}_{4}(X,Y)=X\upharpoonright Y=X\cdot (V\times Y)=\{(a,b)\in X\mid b\in Y\}}
  5. F 5 ( X , Y ) = X ⋅ D ( Y ) = { b ∈ X ∣ ∃ a ( a , b ) ∈ Y } {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {F}}_{5}(X,Y)=X\cdot {\mathfrak {D}}(Y)=\{b\in X\mid \exists a(a,b)\in Y\}}
  6. F 6 ( X , Y ) = X ⋅ Y − 1 = { ( a , b ) ∈ X ∣ ( b , a ) ∈ Y } {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {F}}_{6}(X,Y)=X\cdot Y^{-1}=\{(a,b)\in X\mid (b,a)\in Y\}}
  7. F 7 ( X , Y ) = X ⋅ C n v 2 ( Y ) = { ( a , b , c ) ∈ X ∣ ( a , c , b ) ∈ Y } {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {F}}_{7}(X,Y)=X\cdot {\mathfrak {Cnv}}_{2}(Y)=\{(a,b,c)\in X\mid (a,c,b)\in Y\}}
  8. F 8 ( X , Y ) = X ⋅ C n v 3 ( Y ) = { ( a , b , c ) ∈ X ∣ ( c , a , b ) ∈ Y } {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {F}}_{8}(X,Y)=X\cdot {\mathfrak {Cnv}}_{3}(Y)=\{(a,b,c)\in X\mid (c,a,b)\in Y\}}

The second expression in each line gives Gödel's definition in his original notation, where the dot means intersection, V is the universe, E is the membership relation, D {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {D}}} denotes range and so on. (Here the symbol ↾ {\displaystyle \upharpoonright } is used to restrict range, unlike the contemporary meaning of restriction.)

Jech (2003) uses the following set of 10 Gödel operations.

  1. G 1 ( X , Y ) = { X , Y } {\displaystyle G_{1}(X,Y)=\{X,Y\}}
  2. G 2 ( X , Y ) = X × Y {\displaystyle G_{2}(X,Y)=X\times Y}
  3. G 3 ( X , Y ) = { ( x , y ) ∣ x ∈ X , y ∈ Y , x ∈ y } {\displaystyle G_{3}(X,Y)=\{(x,y)\mid x\in X,y\in Y,x\in y\}}
  4. G 4 ( X , Y ) = X − Y {\displaystyle G_{4}(X,Y)=X-Y}
  5. G 5 ( X , Y ) = X ∩ Y {\displaystyle G_{5}(X,Y)=X\cap Y}
  6. G 6 ( X ) = ∪ X {\displaystyle G_{6}(X)=\cup X}
  7. G 7 ( X ) = dom ( X ) {\displaystyle G_{7}(X)={\text{dom}}(X)}
  8. G 8 ( X ) = { ( x , y ) ∣ ( y , x ) ∈ X } {\displaystyle G_{8}(X)=\{(x,y)\mid (y,x)\in X\}}
  9. G 9 ( X ) = { ( x , y , z ) ∣ ( x , z , y ) ∈ X } {\displaystyle G_{9}(X)=\{(x,y,z)\mid (x,z,y)\in X\}}
  10. G 10 ( X ) = { ( x , y , z ) ∣ ( y , z , x ) ∈ X } {\displaystyle G_{10}(X)=\{(x,y,z)\mid (y,z,x)\in X\}}

The reason for including the functions { ( x , y , z ) ∣ ( x , z , y ) ∈ X } {\displaystyle \{(x,y,z)\mid (x,z,y)\in X\}} and { ( x , y , z ) ∣ ( y , z , x ) ∈ X } {\displaystyle \{(x,y,z)\mid (y,z,x)\in X\}} which permute the entries of an ordered tuple is that, for example, the tuple ( x 1 , x 2 , x 3 , x 4 ) {\displaystyle (x_{1},x_{2},x_{3},x_{4})} can be formed easily from x 1 {\displaystyle x_{1}} and ( x 2 , x 3 , x 4 ) {\displaystyle (x_{2},x_{3},x_{4})} since it equals ( x 1 , ( x 2 , x 3 , x 4 ) ) {\displaystyle (x_{1},(x_{2},x_{3},x_{4}))} , but it is more difficult to form when the entries are given in a different order, such as from x 4 {\displaystyle x_{4}} and ( x 1 , x 2 , x 3 ) {\displaystyle (x_{1},x_{2},x_{3})} .1p. 63

Properties

Gödel's normal form theorem states that if ϕ ( x 1 , … , x n ) {\displaystyle \phi (x_{1},\ldots ,x_{n})} is a formula in the language of set theory with all quantifiers bounded, then the function { ( x 1 , … , x n ) ∈ X ∣ ( x 1 , … , x n ) ∈ ( X 1 × … × X n ) ∧ ϕ ( x 1 , … , x n ) } {\displaystyle \{(x_{1},\ldots ,x_{n})\in X\mid (x_{1},\ldots ,x_{n})\in (X_{1}\times \ldots \times X_{n})\land \phi (x_{1},\ldots ,x_{n})\}} of X 1 {\displaystyle X_{1}} , … {\displaystyle \ldots } , X n {\displaystyle X_{n}} is given by a composition of some Gödel operations. This result is closely related to Jensen's rudimentary functions.2

Jon Barwise showed that a version of Gödel's normal form theorem with his own set of 12 Gödel operations is provable in K P U {\displaystyle \mathrm {KPU} } , a variant of Kripke-Platek set theory admitting urelements.3p. 64

Inline references

References

  1. Barwise, Jon (1975). Admissible Sets and Structures. Perspectives in Mathematical Logic. Springer-Verlag. ISBN 3-540-07451-1. 3-540-07451-1

  2. K. Devlin, An introduction to the fine structure of the constructible hierarchy (1974, p.11). Accessed 2022-02-26. https://core.ac.uk/download/pdf/30905237.pdf

  3. Barwise, Jon (1975). Admissible Sets and Structures. Perspectives in Mathematical Logic. Springer-Verlag. ISBN 3-540-07451-1. 3-540-07451-1