Suppose we are given that P → Q {\displaystyle P\to Q} . Then we have ¬ P ∨ P {\displaystyle \neg P\lor P} by the law of excluded middle (i.e. either P {\displaystyle P} must be true, or P {\displaystyle P} must not be true).
Subsequently, since P → Q {\displaystyle P\to Q} , P {\displaystyle P} can be replaced by Q {\displaystyle Q} in the statement, and thus it follows that ¬ P ∨ Q {\displaystyle \neg P\lor Q} (i.e. either Q {\displaystyle Q} must be true, or P {\displaystyle P} must not be true).
Suppose, conversely, we are given ¬ P ∨ Q {\displaystyle \neg P\lor Q} . Then if P {\displaystyle P} is true, that rules out the first disjunct, so we have Q {\displaystyle Q} . In short, P → Q {\displaystyle P\to Q} .3 However, if P {\displaystyle P} is false, then this entailment fails, because the first disjunct ¬ P {\displaystyle \neg P} is true, which puts no constraint on the second disjunct Q {\displaystyle Q} . Hence, nothing can be said about P → Q {\displaystyle P\to Q} . In sum, the equivalence in the case of false P {\displaystyle P} is only conventional, and hence the formal proof of equivalence is only partial.
This can also be expressed with a truth table:
An example: we are given the conditional fact that if it is a bear, then it can swim. Then, all 4 possibilities in the truth table are compared to that fact.
Thus, the conditional fact can be converted to ¬ P ∨ Q {\displaystyle \neg P\vee Q} , which is "it is not a bear" or "it can swim", where P {\displaystyle P} is the statement "it is a bear" and Q {\displaystyle Q} is the statement "it can swim".
Intuitionistic logic does not treat P → Q {\displaystyle P\to Q} as equivalent to ¬ P ∨ Q {\displaystyle \neg P\vee Q} because
Given P → Q {\displaystyle P\to Q} , one can constructively transform a proof of P {\displaystyle P} into a proof of Q {\displaystyle Q} . In particular, P → P {\displaystyle P\to P} holds in intuitionistic logic. If P → Q ⇒ ¬ P ∨ Q {\displaystyle P\to Q\Rightarrow \neg P\lor Q} would hold, then ¬ P ∨ P {\displaystyle \neg P\lor P} could be derived. However, the latter is the law of excluded middle, which is not accepted by intuitionistic logic (one cannot assume ¬ P ∨ P {\displaystyle \neg P\lor P} without knowing which case applies).
Patrick J. Hurley (1 January 2011). A Concise Introduction to Logic. Cengage Learning. ISBN 978-0-8400-3417-5. 978-0-8400-3417-5 ↩
Copi, Irving M.; Cohen, Carl (2005). Introduction to Logic. Prentice Hall. p. 371. /wiki/Irving_Copi ↩
"Equivalence of a→b and ¬ a ∨ b". Mathematics Stack Exchange. https://math.stackexchange.com/q/243949 ↩