As formulated by David Bloor,3 the strong programme has four indispensable components:
Because the strong programme originated at the 'Science Studies Unit,' University of Edinburgh, it is sometimes termed the Edinburgh School. However, there is also a Bath School associated with Harry Collins that makes similar proposals. In contrast to the Edinburgh School, which emphasizes historical approaches, the Bath School emphasizes microsocial studies of laboratories and experiments.4 The Bath school, however, does depart from the strong programme on some fundamental issues. In the social construction of technology (SCOT) approach developed by Collins' student Trevor Pinch, as well as by the Dutch sociologist Wiebe Bijker, the strong programme was extended to technology. There are SSK-influenced scholars working in science and technology studies programs throughout the world.5
In order to study scientific knowledge from a sociological point of view, the strong programme has adhered to a form of radical relativism. In other words, it argues that – in the social study of institutionalised beliefs about "truth" – it would be unwise to use "truth" as an explanatory resource. To do so would (according to the relativist view) include the answer as part of the question (Barnes 1992), and propound a "whiggish" approach towards the study of history – a narrative of human history as an inevitable march towards truth and enlightenment. Physicists Alan Sokal and Jean Bricmont wrote a scathing critique Fashionable Nonsense of the Strong Programme in 1997 and its reliance on social constructionism.6 Sokal in particular has criticised radical relativism as part of the science wars, on the basis that such an understanding will lead inevitably towards solipsism and postmodernism. has criticised radical relativism as part of the science wars, on the basis that such an understanding will lead inevitably towards solipsism and postmodernism. Markus Seidel attacks the main arguments – underdetermination and norm-circularity – provided by Strong Programme proponents for their relativism.7 It has also been argued that the strong programme has incited climate denial.8
David Bloor, "The strengths of the strong programme." Scientific rationality: The sociological turn (Springer Netherlands, 1984) pp. 75-94. ↩
Donald MacKenzie, "Notes on the science and social relations debate." Capital & Class 5.2 (1981): 47-60. ↩
David Bloor, Knowledge and Social Imagery (1976) ↩
Harry M. Collins, "Introduction: Stages in the empirical programme of relativism." Social studies of science (1981): 3-10. in JSTOR https://www.jstor.org/stable/284733 ↩
Wiebe E. Bijker, et al. The social construction of technological systems: New directions in the sociology and history of technology (MIT press, 2012) ↩
Galaty, David (2022). Modern European Intellectual History: Individuals, Groupings and Technological Change 1800-2000. Bloomsbury Academic. p. 336. ISBN 978-1-350-10539-3. 978-1-350-10539-3 ↩
Markus Seidel Epistemic Relativism. A Constructive Critique, 2014, Palgrave Macmillan ↩
Hansson, Sven Ove (29 August 2020). "Social constructionism and climate science denial". European Journal for Philosophy of Science. 10 (3): 37. doi:10.1007/s13194-020-00305-w. ISSN 1879-4920. https://doi.org/10.1007%2Fs13194-020-00305-w ↩