Let X {\displaystyle X} be an infinite set and let T {\displaystyle {\mathcal {T}}} be the set of subsets of X {\displaystyle X} such that H ∈ T ⟺ X ∖ H is countable, or H = ∅ {\displaystyle H\in {\mathcal {T}}\iff X\setminus H{\mbox{ is countable, or}}\,H=\varnothing } then T {\displaystyle {\mathcal {T}}} is the countable complement toplogy on X {\displaystyle X} , and the topological space T = ( X , T ) {\displaystyle T=(X,{\mathcal {T}})} is a countable complement space.1
Symbolically, the topology is typically written as T = { H ⊆ X : H = ∅ or X ∖ H is countable } . {\displaystyle {\mathcal {T}}=\{H\subseteq X:H=\varnothing {\mbox{ or }}X\setminus H{\mbox{ is countable}}\}.}
Let X {\displaystyle X} be an uncountable set. We define the topology T {\displaystyle {\mathcal {T}}} as all open sets whose complements are countable, along with ∅ {\displaystyle \varnothing } and X {\displaystyle X} itself.2
Let X {\displaystyle X} be the real line. Now let T 1 {\displaystyle {\mathcal {T}}_{1}} be the Euclidean topology and T 2 {\displaystyle {\mathcal {T}}_{2}} be the cocountable topology on X {\displaystyle X} . The cocountable extension topology is the smallest topology generated by T 1 ∪ T 2 {\displaystyle {\mathcal {T}}_{1}\cup {\mathcal {T}}_{2}} .3
By definition, the empty set ∅ {\displaystyle \varnothing } is an element of T {\displaystyle {\mathcal {T}}} . Similarly, the entire set X ∈ T {\displaystyle X\in {\mathcal {T}}} , since the complement of X {\displaystyle X} relative to itself is the empty set, which is vacuously countable.
Suppose A , B ∈ T {\displaystyle A,B\in {\mathcal {T}}} . Let H = A ∩ B {\displaystyle H=A\cap B} . Then
X ∖ H = X ∖ ( A ∩ B ) = ( X ∖ A ) ∪ ( X ∖ B ) {\displaystyle X\setminus H=X\setminus (A\cap B)=(X\setminus A)\cup (X\setminus B)}
by De Morgan's laws. Since A , B ∈ T {\displaystyle A,B\in {\mathcal {T}}} , it follows that X ∖ A {\displaystyle X\setminus A} and X ∖ B {\displaystyle X\setminus B} are both countable. Because the countable union of countable sets is countable, X ∖ H {\displaystyle X\setminus H} is also countable. Therefore, H = A ∩ B ∈ T {\displaystyle H=A\cap B\in {\mathcal {T}}} , as its complement is countable.
Now let U ⊆ T {\displaystyle {\mathcal {U}}\subseteq {\mathcal {T}}} . Then
X ∖ ( ⋃ U ) = ⋂ U ∈ U ( X ∖ U ) {\displaystyle X\setminus \left(\bigcup {\mathcal {U}}\right)=\bigcap _{U\in {\mathcal {U}}}(X\setminus U)}
again by De Morgan's laws. For each U ∈ U {\displaystyle U\in {\mathcal {U}}} , X ∖ U {\displaystyle X\setminus U} is countable. The countable intersection of countable sets is also countable (assuming U {\displaystyle {\mathcal {U}}} is countable), so S ∖ ( ⋃ U ) {\displaystyle S\setminus \left(\bigcup {\mathcal {U}}\right)} is countable. Thus, ⋃ U ∈ T {\displaystyle \bigcup {\mathcal {U}}\in {\mathcal {T}}} .
Since all three open set axioms are met, T {\displaystyle {\mathcal {T}}} is a topology on X {\displaystyle X} .4
Every set X {\displaystyle X} with the cocountable topology is Lindelöf, since every nonempty open set omits only countably many points of X {\displaystyle X} . It is also T1, as all singletons are closed.
If X {\displaystyle X} is an uncountable set, then any two nonempty open sets intersect, hence, the space is not Hausdorff. However, in the cocountable topology all convergent sequences are eventually constant, so limits are unique. Since compact sets in X {\displaystyle X} are finite subsets, all compact subsets are closed, another condition usually related to the Hausdorff separation axiom.
The cocountable topology on a countable set is the discrete topology. The cocountable topology on an uncountable set is hyperconnected, thus connected, locally connected and pseudocompact, but neither weakly countably compact nor countably metacompact, hence not compact.
Munkres, James Raymond (2000). Topology (2nd ed.). Upper Saddle River (N. J.): Prentice Hall. ISBN 0-13-181629-2. 0-13-181629-2 ↩
Steen, Lynn Arthur; Seebach, Jr., J. Arthur (1978). "2". Counterexamples in Topology (2nd ed.). New York, NY: Springer New York. p. 50. ISBN 978-1-4612-6290-9. 978-1-4612-6290-9 ↩
Steen, Lynn Arthur; Seebach, Jr., J. Arthur (1978). "2". Counterexamples in Topology (2nd ed.). New York, NY: Springer New York. p. 85. ISBN 978-1-4612-6290-9. 978-1-4612-6290-9 ↩
Steen, Lynn Arthur; Seebach, J. Arthur (1978). "20". Counterexamples in Topology (2nd ed.). New York, NY: Springer New York. ISBN 978-0-387-90312-5. 978-0-387-90312-5 ↩