The terms "thought" and "thinking" refer to a wide variety of psychological activities. In their most common sense, they are understood as conscious processes that can happen independently of sensory stimulation. This includes various different mental processes, like considering an idea or proposition or judging it to be true. In this sense, memory and imagination are forms of thought but perception is not. In a more restricted sense, only the most paradigmatic cases are considered thought. These involve conscious processes that are conceptual or linguistic and sufficiently abstract, like judging, inferring, problem solving, and deliberating. Sometimes the terms "thought" and "thinking" are understood in a very wide sense as referring to any form of mental process, conscious or unconscious. In this sense, they may be used synonymously with the term "mind". This usage is encountered, for example, in the Cartesian tradition, where minds are understood as thinking things, and in the cognitive sciences. But this sense may include the restriction that such processes have to lead to intelligent behavior to be considered thought. A contrast sometimes found in the academic literature is that between thinking and feeling. In this context, thinking is associated with a sober, dispassionate, and rational approach to its topic while feeling involves a direct emotional engagement.
The terms "thought" and "thinking" can also be used to refer not to the mental processes themselves but to mental states or systems of ideas brought about by these processes. In this sense, they are often synonymous with the term "belief" and its cognates and may refer to the mental states which either belong to an individual or are common among a certain group of people. Discussions of thought in the academic literature often leave it implicit which sense of the term they have in mind.
Various theories of thinking have been proposed. They aim to capture the characteristic features of thinking. The theories listed here are not exclusive: it may be possible to combine some without leading to a contradiction.
Conceptualism is closely related to Aristotelianism. It states that thinking consists in mentally evoking concepts. Some of these concepts may be innate, but most have to be learned through abstraction from sense experience before they can be used in thought.
It has been argued against these views that they have problems in accounting for the logical form of thought. For example, to think that it will either rain or snow, it is not sufficient to instantiate the essences of rain and snow or to evoke the corresponding concepts. The reason for this is that the disjunctive relation between the rain and the snow is not captured this way. Another problem shared by these positions is the difficulty of giving a satisfying account of how essences or concepts are learned by the mind through abstraction.
Inner speech theory has a strong initial plausibility since introspection suggests that indeed many thoughts are accompanied by inner speech. But its opponents usually contend that this is not true for all types of thinking. It has been argued, for example, that forms of daydreaming constitute non-linguistic thought. This issue is relevant to the question of whether animals have the capacity to think. If thinking is necessarily tied to language then this would suggest that there is an important gap between humans and animals since only humans have a sufficiently complex language. But the existence of non-linguistic thoughts suggests that this gap may not be that big and that some animals do indeed think.
There are various theories about the relation between language and thought. One prominent version in contemporary philosophy is called the language of thought hypothesis. It states that thinking happens in the medium of a mental language. This language, often referred to as Mentalese, is similar to regular languages in various respects: it is composed of words that are connected to each other in syntactic ways to form sentences. This claim does not merely rest on an intuitive analogy between language and thought. Instead, it provides a clear definition of the features a representational system has to embody in order to have a linguistic structure. On the level of syntax, the representational system has to possess two types of representations: atomic and compound representations. Atomic representations are basic whereas compound representations are constituted either by other compound representations or by atomic representations. On the level of semantics, the semantic content or the meaning of the compound representations should depend on the semantic contents of its constituents. A representational system is linguistically structured if it fulfills these two requirements.
The language of thought hypothesis states that the same is true for thinking in general. This would mean that thought is composed of certain atomic representational constituents that can be combined as described above. Apart from this abstract characterization, no further concrete claims are made about how human thought is implemented by the brain or which other similarities to natural language it has. The language of thought hypothesis was first introduced by Jerry Fodor. He argues in favor of this claim by holding that it constitutes the best explanation of the characteristic features of thinking. One of these features is productivity: a system of representations is productive if it can generate an infinite number of unique representations based on a low number of atomic representations. This applies to thought since human beings are capable of entertaining an infinite number of distinct thoughts even though their mental capacities are quite limited. Other characteristic features of thinking include systematicity and inferential coherence. Fodor argues that the language of thought hypothesis is true as it explains how thought can have these features and because there is no good alternative explanation. Some arguments against the language of thought hypothesis are based on neural networks, which are able to produce intelligent behavior without depending on representational systems. Other objections focus on the idea that some mental representations happen non-linguistically, for example, in the form of maps or images.
Computationalists have been especially interested in the language of thought hypothesis since it provides ways to close the gap between thought in the human brain and computational processes implemented by computers. The reason for this is that processes over representations that respect syntax and semantics, like inferences according to the modus ponens, can be implemented by physical systems using causal relations. The same linguistic systems may be implemented through different material systems, like brains or computers. In this way, computers can think.
One form of associationism is imagism. It states that thinking involves entertaining a sequence of images where earlier images conjure up later images based on the laws of association. One problem with this view is that we can think about things that we cannot imagine. This is especially relevant when the thought involves very complex objects or infinities, which is common, for example, in mathematical thought. One criticism directed at associationism in general is that its claim is too far-reaching. There is wide agreement that associative processes as studied by associationists play some role in how thought unfolds. But the claim that this mechanism is sufficient to understand all thought or all mental processes is usually not accepted.
One problem for behaviorism is that the same entity often behaves differently despite being in the same situation as before. This problem consists in the fact that individual thoughts or mental states usually do not correspond to one particular behavior. So thinking that the pie is tasty does not automatically lead to eating the pie, since various other mental states may still inhibit this behavior, for example, the belief that it would be impolite to do so or that the pie is poisoned.
Computationalist theories of thought are sometimes divided into functionalist and representationalist approaches. Functionalist approaches define mental states through their causal roles but allow both external and internal events in their causal network. Thought may be seen as a form of program that can be executed in the same way by many different systems, including humans, animals, and even robots. According to one such view, whether something is a thought only depends on its role "in producing further internal states and verbal outputs". Representationalism, on the other hand, focuses on the representational features of mental states and defines thoughts as sequences of intentional mental states. In this sense, computationalism is often combined with the language of thought hypothesis by interpreting these sequences as symbols whose order is governed by syntactic rules.
Various arguments have been raised against computationalism. In one sense, it seems trivial since almost any physical system can be described as executing computations and therefore as thinking. For example, it has been argued that the molecular movements in a regular wall can be understood as computing an algorithm since they are "isomorphic to the formal structure of the program" in question under the right interpretation. This would lead to the implausible conclusion that the wall is thinking. Another objection focuses on the idea that computationalism captures only some aspects of thought but is unable to account for other crucial aspects of human cognition.
A great variety of types of thinking are discussed in the academic literature. A common approach divides them into those forms that aim at the creation of theoretical knowledge and those that aim at producing actions or correct decisions, but there is no universally accepted taxonomy summarizing all these types.
Other theories of judgment focus more on the relation between the judged proposition and reality. According to Franz Brentano, a judgment is either a belief or a disbelief in the existence of some entity. In this sense, there are only two fundamental forms of judgment: "A exists" and "A does not exist". When applied to the sentence "all men are mortal", the entity in question is "immortal men", of whom it is said that they do not exist. Important for Brentano is the distinction between the mere representation of the content of the judgment and the affirmation or the denial of the content. The mere representation of a proposition is often referred to as "entertaining a proposition". This is the case, for example, when one considers a proposition but has not yet made up one's mind about whether it is true or false. The term "thinking" can refer both to judging and to mere entertaining. This difference is often explicit in the way the thought is expressed: "thinking that" usually involves a judgment whereas "thinking about" refers to the neutral representation of a proposition without an accompanying belief. In this case, the proposition is merely entertained but not yet judged. Some forms of thinking may involve the representation of objects without any propositions, as when someone is thinking about their grandmother.
Reasoning is one of the most paradigmatic forms of thinking. It is the process of drawing conclusions from premises or evidence. Types of reasoning can be divided into deductive and non-deductive reasoning. Deductive reasoning is governed by certain rules of inference, which guarantee the truth of the conclusion if the premises are true. For example, given the premises "all men are mortal" and "Socrates is a man", it follows deductively that "Socrates is mortal". Non-deductive reasoning, also referred to as defeasible reasoning or non-monotonic reasoning, is still rationally compelling but the truth of the conclusion is not ensured by the truth of the premises. Induction is one form of non-deductive reasoning, for example, when one concludes that "the sun will rise tomorrow" based on one's experiences of all the previous days. Other forms of non-deductive reasoning include the inference to the best explanation and analogical reasoning.
Obstacles to problem solving can arise from the thinker's failure to take certain possibilities into account by fixating on one specific course of action. There are important differences between how novices and experts solve problems. For example, experts tend to allocate more time for conceptualizing the problem and work with more complex representations whereas novices tend to devote more time to executing putative solutions.
Various theorists emphasize the practical nature of thought, i.e. that thinking is usually guided by some kind of task it aims to solve. In this sense, thinking has been compared to trial-and-error seen in animal behavior when faced with a new problem. On this view, the important difference is that this process happens inwardly as a form of simulation. This process is often much more efficient since once the solution is found in thought, only the behavior corresponding to the found solution has to be outwardly carried out and not all the others.
It has been argued that conscious and unconscious thoughts differ not just concerning their relation to experience but also concerning their capacities. According to unconscious thought theorists, for example, conscious thought excels at simple problems with few variables but is outperformed by unconscious thought when complex problems with many variables are involved. This is sometimes explained through the claim that the number of items one can consciously think about at the same time is rather limited whereas unconscious thought lacks such limitations. But other researchers have rejected the claim that unconscious thought is often superior to conscious thought. Other suggestions for the difference between the two forms of thinking include that conscious thought tends to follow formal logical laws while unconscious thought relies more on associative processing and that only conscious thinking is conceptually articulated and happens through the medium of language.
Phenomenologists are also concerned with the characteristic features of the experience of thinking. Making a judgment is one of the prototypical forms of cognitive phenomenology. It involves epistemic agency, in which a proposition is entertained, evidence for and against it is considered, and, based on this reasoning, the proposition is either affirmed or rejected. It is sometimes argued that the experience of truth is central to thinking, i.e. that thinking aims at representing how the world is. It shares this feature with perception but differs from it in the way how it represents the world: without the use of sensory contents.
One of the characteristic features often ascribed to thinking and judging is that they are predicative experiences, in contrast to the pre-predicative experience found in immediate perception. On such a view, various aspects of perceptual experience resemble judgments without being judgments in the strict sense. For example, the perceptual experience of the front of a house brings with it various expectations about aspects of the house not directly seen, like the size and shape of its other sides. This process is sometimes referred to as apperception. These expectations resemble judgments and can be wrong. This would be the case when it turns out upon walking around the "house" that it is no house at all but only a front facade of a house with nothing behind it. In this case, the perceptual expectations are frustrated and the perceiver is surprised. There is disagreement as to whether these pre-predicative aspects of regular perception should be understood as a form of cognitive phenomenology involving thinking. This issue is also important for understanding the relation between thought and language. The reason for this is that the pre-predicative expectations do not depend on language, which is sometimes taken as an example for non-linguistic thought. Various theorists have argued that pre-predicative experience is more basic or fundamental since predicative experience is in some sense built on top of it and therefore depends on it.
Another way how phenomenologists have tried to distinguish the experience of thinking from other types of experiences is in relation to empty intentions in contrast to intuitive intentions. In this context, "intention" means that some kind of object is experienced. In intuitive intentions, the object is presented through sensory contents. Empty intentions, on the other hand, present their object in a more abstract manner without the help of sensory contents. So when perceiving a sunset, it is presented through sensory contents. The same sunset can also be presented non-intuitively when merely thinking about it without the help of sensory contents. In these cases, the same properties are ascribed to objects. The difference between these modes of presentation concerns not what properties are ascribed to the presented object but how the object is presented. Because of this commonality, it is possible for representations belonging to different modes to overlap or to diverge. For example, when searching one's glasses one may think to oneself that one left them on the kitchen table. This empty intention of the glasses lying on the kitchen table are then intuitively fulfilled when one sees them lying there upon arriving in the kitchen. This way, a perception can confirm or refute a thought depending on whether the empty intuitions are later fulfilled or not.
The above reflects a classical, functional description of how we work as cognitive, thinking systems. However the apparently irresolvable mind–body problem is said to be overcome, and bypassed, by the embodied cognition approach, with its roots in the work of Heidegger, Piaget, Vygotsky, Merleau-Ponty and the pragmatist John Dewey.
This approach states that the classical approach of separating the mind and analysing its processes is misguided: instead, we should see that the mind, actions of an embodied agent, and the environment it perceives and envisions, are all parts of a whole which determine each other. Therefore, functional analysis of the mind alone will always leave us with the mind–body problem which cannot be solved.
Psychologists have concentrated on thinking as an intellectual exertion aimed at finding an answer to a question or the solution of a practical problem. Cognitive psychology is a branch of psychology that investigates internal mental processes such as problem solving, memory, and language; all of which are used in thinking. The school of thought arising from this approach is known as cognitivism, which is interested in how people mentally represent information processing. It had its foundations in the Gestalt psychology of Max Wertheimer, Wolfgang Köhler, and Kurt Koffka, and in the work of Jean Piaget, who provided a theory of stages/phases that describes children's cognitive development.
For psychoanalysis, the unconscious does not include all that is not conscious, rather only what is actively repressed from conscious thought or what the person is averse to knowing consciously. In a sense this view places the self in relationship to their unconscious as an adversary, warring with itself to keep what is unconscious hidden. If a person feels pain, all he can think of is alleviating the pain. Any of his desires, to get rid of pain or enjoy something, command the mind what to do. For Freud, the unconscious was a repository for socially unacceptable ideas, wishes or desires, traumatic memories, and painful emotions put out of mind by the mechanism of psychological repression. However, the contents did not necessarily have to be solely negative. In the psychoanalytic view, the unconscious is a force that can only be recognized by its effects—it expresses itself in the symptom.
While there is a very wide acceptance of these three laws among logicians, they are not universally accepted. Aristotle, for example, held that there are some cases in which the law of excluded middle is false. This concerns primarily uncertain future events. On his view, it is currently "not ... either true or false that there will be a naval battle tomorrow". Modern intuitionist logic also rejects the law of excluded middle. This rejection is based on the idea that mathematical truth depends on verification through a proof. The law fails for cases where no such proof is possible, which exist in every sufficiently strong formal system, according to Gödel's incompleteness theorems. Dialetheists, on the other hand, reject the law of contradiction by holding that some propositions are both true and false. One motivation of this position is to avoid certain paradoxes in classical logic and set theory, like the liar's paradox and Russell's paradox. One of its problems is to find a formulation that circumvents the principle of explosion, i.e. that anything follows from a contradiction.
Counterfactual thinking plays an important role since we evaluate the world around us not only by what actually happened but also by what could have happened. Humans have a greater tendency to engage in counterfactual thinking after something bad happened because of some kind of action the agent performed. In this sense, many regrets are associated with counterfactual thinking in which the agent contemplates how a better outcome could have been obtained if only they had acted differently. These cases are known as upward counterfactuals, in contrast to downward counterfactuals, in which the counterfactual scenario is worse than actuality. Upward counterfactual thinking is usually experienced as unpleasant, since it presents the actual circumstances in a bad light. This contrasts with the positive emotions associated with downward counterfactual thinking. But both forms are important since it is possible to learn from them and to adjust one's behavior accordingly to get better results in the future.
Thought experiments are employed for various purposes, for example, for entertainment, education, or as arguments for or against theories. Most discussions focus on their use as arguments. This use is found in fields like philosophy, the natural sciences, and history. It is controversial since there is a lot of disagreement concerning the epistemic status of thought experiments, i.e. how reliable they are as evidence supporting or refuting a theory. Central to the rejection of this usage is the fact that they pretend to be a source of knowledge without the need to leave one's armchair in search of any new empirical data. Defenders of thought experiments usually contend that the intuitions underlying and guiding the thought experiments are, at least in some cases, reliable. But thought experiments can also fail if they are not properly supported by intuitions or if they go beyond what the intuitions support. In the latter sense, sometimes counter thought experiments are proposed that modify the original scenario in slight ways in order to show that initial intuitions cannot survive this change. Various taxonomies of thought experiments have been suggested. They can be distinguished, for example, by whether they are successful or not, by the discipline that uses them, by their role in a theory, or by whether they accept or modify the actual laws of physics.
Critical thinking plays an important role in education: fostering the student's ability to think critically is often seen as an important educational goal. In this sense, it is important to convey not just a set of true beliefs to the student but also the ability to draw one's own conclusions and to question pre-existing beliefs. The abilities and dispositions learned this way may profit not just the individual but also society at large. Critics of the emphasis on critical thinking in education have argued that there is no universal form of correct thinking. Instead, they contend that different subject matters rely on different standards and education should focus on imparting these subject-specific skills instead of trying to teach universal methods of thinking. Other objections are based on the idea that critical thinking and the attitude underlying it involve various unjustified biases, like egocentrism, distanced objectivity, indifference, and an overemphasis of the theoretical in contrast to the practical.
The effects of positive thinking are not yet thoroughly researched, but some studies suggest that there is a correlation between positive thinking and well-being. For example, students and pregnant women with a positive outlook tend to be better at dealing with stressful situations. This is sometimes explained by pointing out that stress is not inherent in stressful situations but depends on the agent's interpretation of the situation. Reduced stress may therefore be found in positive thinkers because they tend to see such situations in a more positive light. But the effects also include the practical domain in that positive thinkers tend to employ healthier coping strategies when faced with difficult situations. This effects, for example, the time needed to fully recover from surgeries and the tendency to resume physical exercise afterward.
But it has been argued that whether positive thinking actually leads to positive outcomes depends on various other factors. Without these factors, it may lead to negative results. For example, the tendency of optimists to keep striving in difficult situations can backfire if the course of events is outside the agent's control. Another danger associated with positive thinking is that it may remain only on the level of unrealistic fantasies and thereby fail to make a positive practical contribution to the agent's life. Pessimism, on the other hand, may have positive effects since it can mitigate disappointments by anticipating failures.
Positive thinking is a recurrent topic in the self-help literature. Here, often the claim is made that one can significantly improve one's life by trying to think positively, even if this means fostering beliefs that are contrary to evidence. Such claims and the effectiveness of the suggested methods are controversial and have been criticized due to their lack of scientific evidence. In the New Thought movement, positive thinking figures in the law of attraction, the pseudoscientific claim that positive thoughts can directly influence the external world by attracting positive outcomes.
"Thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 14 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/thought
Random House Webster's Unabridged Dictionary, 2nd ed., 2001, Published by Random House, Inc., ISBN 978-0-375-42599-8, p. 1975 /wiki/ISBN_(identifier)
Webster's II New College Dictionary, Webster Staff, Webster, Houghton Mifflin Company, 2nd ed., illustrated, revised Published by Houghton Mifflin Harcourt, 1999, ISBN 978-0-395-96214-5, p. 1147 /wiki/ISBN_(identifier)
Breyer, Thiemo; Gutland, Christopher (2015). "Introduction". Phenomenology of Thinking: Philosophical Investigations into the Character of Cognitive Experiences. Routledge. pp. 1–24. https://philpapers.org/rec/BREI-15
Nida-rümelin, Martine (2010). "Thinking Without Language. A Phenomenological Argument for Its Possibility and Existence". Grazer Philosophische Studien. 81 (1): 55–75. doi:10.1163/9789042030190_005. https://philpapers.org/rec/NIDTWL
Crowell, Steven (2015). "What Is It to Think?". In Breyer, Thiemo; Gutland, Christopher (eds.). Phenomenology of Thinking. Routledge. pp. 189–212. doi:10.4324/9781315697734. ISBN 978-1-315-69773-4. 978-1-315-69773-4
"Thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 14 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/thought
Mole, Christopher (2021). "Attention: 2.3 Coherence Theories". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 21 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/attention/#CohThe
Katsafanas, Paul (2015). "Nietzsche on the Nature of the Unconscious". Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy. 58 (3): 327–352. doi:10.1080/0020174X.2013.855658. S2CID 38776513. https://philpapers.org/rec/KATNOT
Garrison, Katie E.; Handley, Ian M. (2017). "Not Merely Experiential: Unconscious Thought Can Be Rational". Frontiers in Psychology. 8: 1096. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2017.01096. ISSN 1664-1078. PMC 5498519. PMID 28729844. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC5498519
Dijksterhuis, Ap; Nordgren, Loran F. (1 June 2006). "A Theory of Unconscious Thought". Perspectives on Psychological Science. 1 (2): 95–109. doi:10.1111/j.1745-6916.2006.00007.x. hdl:2066/55863. ISSN 1745-6916. PMID 26151465. S2CID 7875280. https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/10.1111/j.1745-6916.2006.00007.x
Crowell, Steven (2015). "What Is It to Think?". In Breyer, Thiemo; Gutland, Christopher (eds.). Phenomenology of Thinking. Routledge. pp. 189–212. doi:10.4324/9781315697734. ISBN 978-1-315-69773-4. 978-1-315-69773-4
Skirry, Justin. "Descartes, Rene: Mind-Body Distinction". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 17 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/descmind/
Smith, Kurt (2021). "Descartes' Theory of Ideas: 1. Ideas Understood as Modes of Thinking". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 21 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/descartes-ideas/#thoughts
Baum, Eric B. (2004). "1. Introduction". What Is Thought?. Cambridge MA: Bradford Book/MIT Press. https://philpapers.org/rec/BAUWIT
Block, Ned (1981). "Psychologism and Behaviorism". Philosophical Review. 90 (1): 5–43. doi:10.2307/2184371. JSTOR 2184371. https://philpapers.org/rec/BLOPAB
Romer, Paul M. (May 2000). "Thinking and Feeling". American Economic Review. 90 (2): 439–443. doi:10.1257/aer.90.2.439. ISSN 0002-8282. https://www.aeaweb.org/articles?id=10.1257/aer.90.2.439
Planalp, Sally; Fitness, Julie (1 December 1999). "Thinking/Feeling about Social and Personal Relationships". Journal of Social and Personal Relationships. 16 (6): 731–750. doi:10.1177/0265407599166004. ISSN 0265-4075. S2CID 145750153. https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/abs/10.1177/0265407599166004
Phelan, Mark; Arico, Adam; Nichols, Shaun (2013). "Thinking Things and Feeling Things: On an Alleged Discontinuity in Folk Metaphysics of Mind". Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. 12 (4): 703–725. doi:10.1007/s11097-012-9278-7. S2CID 15856600. https://philpapers.org/rec/PHETTA
"The American Heritage Dictionary entry: thought". www.ahdictionary.com. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing. Retrieved 23 October 2021. https://www.ahdictionary.com/word/search.html?q=thought
Mandelbaum, Eric (2014). "Thinking is Believing". Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy. 57 (1): 55–96. doi:10.1080/0020174X.2014.858417. S2CID 52968342. https://philpapers.org/rec/MANTIB-2
"The American Heritage Dictionary entry: think". www.ahdictionary.com. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing. Retrieved 23 October 2021. https://www.ahdictionary.com/word/search.html?q=think
Harper, Douglas. "Etymology of Thought". Online Etymology Dictionary. Retrieved 2009-05-22. http://www.etymonline.com/index.php?search=Thought
Borchert, Donald (2006). "Thinking". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. https://philpapers.org/rec/BORMEO
Borchert, Donald (2006). "Thinking". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. https://philpapers.org/rec/BORMEO
Woolf, Raphael (1 January 2013). "Plato and the Norms of Thought". Mind. 122 (485): 171–216. doi:10.1093/mind/fzt012. ISSN 0026-4423. https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/122/485/171/961176
Langland-Hassan, Peter; Vicente, Agustin (2018). "Introduction". Inner Speech: New Voices. Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://philpapers.org/rec/LANISN
Kraut, Richard (2017). "Plato". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 24 April 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato/
Brickhouse, Thomas; Smith, Nicholas D. "Plato: 6b. The Theory of Forms". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 24 April 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/plato/#SH6b
Nehamas, Alexander (1975). "Plato on the Imperfection of the Sensible World". American Philosophical Quarterly. 12 (2): 105–117. ISSN 0003-0481. JSTOR 20009565. https://www.jstor.org/stable/20009565
Woolf, Raphael (1 January 2013). "Plato and the Norms of Thought". Mind. 122 (485): 171–216. doi:10.1093/mind/fzt012. ISSN 0026-4423. https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/122/485/171/961176
Borchert, Donald (2006). "Thinking". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. https://philpapers.org/rec/BORMEO
Woolf, Raphael (1 January 2013). "Plato and the Norms of Thought". Mind. 122 (485): 171–216. doi:10.1093/mind/fzt012. ISSN 0026-4423. https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/122/485/171/961176
Woolf, Raphael (1 January 2013). "Plato and the Norms of Thought". Mind. 122 (485): 171–216. doi:10.1093/mind/fzt012. ISSN 0026-4423. https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/122/485/171/961176
Borchert, Donald (2006). "Thinking". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. https://philpapers.org/rec/BORMEO
Borchert, Donald (2006). "Thinking". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. https://philpapers.org/rec/BORMEO
Sellars, Wilfrid (1949). "Aristotelian Philosophies of Mind". Philosophy for The Future, The Quest of Modern Materialism. http://www.ditext.com/sellars/apm.html
Klima, Gyula (2017). "The Medieval Problem of Universals: 1. Introduction". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 21 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/universals-medieval/#Intr
Sellars, Wilfrid (1949). "Aristotelian Philosophies of Mind". Philosophy for The Future, The Quest of Modern Materialism. http://www.ditext.com/sellars/apm.html
Borchert, Donald (2006). "Thinking". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. https://philpapers.org/rec/BORMEO
Borchert, Donald (2006). "Thinking". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. https://philpapers.org/rec/BORMEO
Borchert, Donald (2006). "Thinking". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. https://philpapers.org/rec/BORMEO
Crowell, Steven (2015). "What Is It to Think?". In Breyer, Thiemo; Gutland, Christopher (eds.). Phenomenology of Thinking. Routledge. pp. 189–212. doi:10.4324/9781315697734. ISBN 978-1-315-69773-4. 978-1-315-69773-4
Harman, Gilbert (1973). "4. Thought and meaning". Thought. Princeton University Press. https://philpapers.org/rec/HART
Langland-Hassan, Peter; Vicente, Agustin (2018). "Introduction". Inner Speech: New Voices. Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://philpapers.org/rec/LANISN
"Thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 14 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/thought
Borchert, Donald (2006). "Thinking". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. https://philpapers.org/rec/BORMEO
Roessler, Johannes (2016). "Thinking, Inner Speech, and Self-Awareness". Review of Philosophy and Psychology. 7 (3): 541–557. doi:10.1007/s13164-015-0267-y. S2CID 15028459. https://philpapers.org/rec/ROETIS-2
Langland-Hassan, Peter; Vicente, Agustin (2018). "Introduction". Inner Speech: New Voices. Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://philpapers.org/rec/LANISN
"Thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 14 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/thought
Harman, Gilbert (1973). "4. Thought and meaning". Thought. Princeton University Press. https://philpapers.org/rec/HART
Rescorla, Michael (2019). "The Language of Thought Hypothesis". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/language-thought/
Borchert, Donald (2006). "Thinking". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. https://philpapers.org/rec/BORMEO
Nida-rümelin, Martine (2010). "Thinking Without Language. A Phenomenological Argument for Its Possibility and Existence". Grazer Philosophische Studien. 81 (1): 55–75. doi:10.1163/9789042030190_005. https://philpapers.org/rec/NIDTWL
Bermudez, Jose Luis (2003). Thinking Without Words. Oxford University Press USA. https://philpapers.org/rec/LUITWW
Lohmar, Dieter (2012). Zahavi, Dan (ed.). "Language and non-linguistic thinking". The Oxford Handbook of Contemporary Phenomenology. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199594900.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-959490-0. 978-0-19-959490-0
Bermudez, Jose Luis (2003). Thinking Without Words. Oxford University Press USA. https://philpapers.org/rec/LUITWW
Andrews, Kristin; Monsó, Susana (2021). "Animal Cognition: 3.4 Thought". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 25 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/cognition-animal/#Thou
Premack, David (28 August 2007). "Human and animal cognition: Continuity and discontinuity". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 104 (35): 13861–13867. Bibcode:2007PNAS..10413861P. doi:10.1073/pnas.0706147104. ISSN 0027-8424. PMC 1955772. PMID 17717081. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC1955772
Harman, Gilbert (1973). "4. Thought and meaning". Thought. Princeton University Press. https://philpapers.org/rec/HART
Rescorla, Michael (2019). "The Language of Thought Hypothesis". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/language-thought/
Katz, Matthew. "Language of Thought Hypothesis". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 27 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/lot-hypo/
Aydede, Murat. "Oxford Bibliographies: Language of Thought". Retrieved 27 October 2021. https://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/view/document/obo-9780195396577/obo-9780195396577-0151.xml
Fodor, Jerry A. (2008). Lot 2: The Language of Thought Revisited. Oxford University Press. https://philpapers.org/rec/FODLT
Harman, Gilbert (1973). "4. Thought and meaning". Thought. Princeton University Press. https://philpapers.org/rec/HART
Rescorla, Michael (2019). "The Language of Thought Hypothesis". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/language-thought/
Katz, Matthew. "Language of Thought Hypothesis". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 27 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/lot-hypo/
Aydede, Murat. "Oxford Bibliographies: Language of Thought". Retrieved 27 October 2021. https://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/view/document/obo-9780195396577/obo-9780195396577-0151.xml
Katz, Matthew. "Language of Thought Hypothesis". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 27 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/lot-hypo/
Rescorla, Michael (2019). "The Language of Thought Hypothesis". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/language-thought/
Aydede, Murat. "Oxford Bibliographies: Language of Thought". Retrieved 27 October 2021. https://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/view/document/obo-9780195396577/obo-9780195396577-0151.xml
Katz, Matthew. "Language of Thought Hypothesis". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 27 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/lot-hypo/
Rescorla, Michael (2019). "The Language of Thought Hypothesis". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/language-thought/
Aydede, Murat. "Oxford Bibliographies: Language of Thought". Retrieved 27 October 2021. https://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/view/document/obo-9780195396577/obo-9780195396577-0151.xml
Katz, Matthew. "Language of Thought Hypothesis". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 27 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/lot-hypo/
Rescorla, Michael (2019). "The Language of Thought Hypothesis". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/language-thought/
Aydede, Murat. "Oxford Bibliographies: Language of Thought". Retrieved 27 October 2021. https://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/view/document/obo-9780195396577/obo-9780195396577-0151.xml
Katz, Matthew. "Language of Thought Hypothesis". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 27 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/lot-hypo/
Rescorla, Michael (2019). "The Language of Thought Hypothesis". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/language-thought/
Borchert, Donald (2006). "Language of thought". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. https://www.encyclopedia.com/humanities/encyclopedias-almanacs-transcripts-and-maps/language-thought
Katz, Matthew. "Language of Thought Hypothesis". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 27 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/lot-hypo/
Rescorla, Michael (2019). "The Language of Thought Hypothesis". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/language-thought/
Katz, Matthew. "Language of Thought Hypothesis". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 27 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/lot-hypo/
Katz, Matthew. "Language of Thought Hypothesis". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 27 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/lot-hypo/
Rescorla, Michael (2019). "The Language of Thought Hypothesis". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/language-thought/
Borchert, Donald (2006). "Language of thought". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. https://www.encyclopedia.com/humanities/encyclopedias-almanacs-transcripts-and-maps/language-thought
Rescorla, Michael (2019). "The Language of Thought Hypothesis". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/language-thought/
Katz, Matthew. "Language of Thought Hypothesis". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 27 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/lot-hypo/
Borchert, Donald (2006). "Language of thought". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. https://www.encyclopedia.com/humanities/encyclopedias-almanacs-transcripts-and-maps/language-thought
Katz, Matthew. "Language of Thought Hypothesis". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 27 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/lot-hypo/
Katz, Matthew. "Language of Thought Hypothesis". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 27 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/lot-hypo/
Rescorla, Michael (2019). "The Language of Thought Hypothesis". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/language-thought/
Katz, Matthew. "Language of Thought Hypothesis". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 27 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/lot-hypo/
Rescorla, Michael (2019). "The Language of Thought Hypothesis". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/language-thought/
Milkowski, Marcin. "Computational Theory of Mind". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 21 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/compmind/
Katz, Matthew. "Language of Thought Hypothesis". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 27 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/lot-hypo/
Rescorla, Michael (2019). "The Language of Thought Hypothesis". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/language-thought/
"Thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 14 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/thought
Doorey, Marie. "Conditioning". The Gale Encyclopedia of Science. https://www.encyclopedia.com/medicine/psychology/psychology-and-psychiatry/conditioning
Van der Veldt, J. H. "Associationism". New Catholic Encyclopedia. https://www.encyclopedia.com/medicine/psychology/psychology-and-psychiatry/associationism
"Thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 14 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/thought
Mandelbaum, Eric (2020). "Associationist Theories of Thought". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 23 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/associationist-thought/
Mandelbaum, Eric (2020). "Associationist Theories of Thought". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 23 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/associationist-thought/
"Thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 14 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/thought
Doorey, Marie. "Conditioning". The Gale Encyclopedia of Science. https://www.encyclopedia.com/medicine/psychology/psychology-and-psychiatry/conditioning
Mandelbaum, Eric (2020). "Associationist Theories of Thought". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 23 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/associationist-thought/
Mandelbaum, Eric (2020). "Associationist Theories of Thought". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 23 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/associationist-thought/
Borchert, Donald (2006). "Thinking". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. https://philpapers.org/rec/BORMEO
Borchert, Donald (2006). "Thinking". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. https://philpapers.org/rec/BORMEO
Van der Veldt, J. H. "Associationism". New Catholic Encyclopedia. https://www.encyclopedia.com/medicine/psychology/psychology-and-psychiatry/associationism
Mandelbaum, Eric (2020). "Associationist Theories of Thought". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 23 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/associationist-thought/
Rescorla, Michael (2020). "The Computational Theory of Mind". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 22 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/computational-mind/
Lazzeri, Filipe (2019-08-16). "O que é Behaviorismo sobre a mente?". Principia (in Portuguese). 23 (2): 249–277. doi:10.5007/1808-1711.2019v23n2p249. ISSN 1808-1711. S2CID 212888121. https://doi.org/10.5007%2F1808-1711.2019v23n2p249
Graham, George (2019). "Behaviorism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 31 May 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/behaviorism/
Graham, George (2019). "Behaviorism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 31 May 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/behaviorism/
Audet, Jean-Nicolas; Lefebvre, Louis (18 February 2017). "What's flexible in behavioral flexibility?". Behavioral Ecology. 28 (4): 943–947. doi:10.1093/beheco/arx007. ISSN 1045-2249. https://academic.oup.com/beheco/article/28/4/943/3003315
Reese, Hayne W. (2000). "Thinking as the Behaviorist Views It". Behavioral Development Bulletin. 9 (1): 10–12. doi:10.1037/h0100531. https://psycnet.apa.org/fulltext/2014-55592-003.html
"Thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 14 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/thought
Reese, Hayne W. (2000). "Thinking as the Behaviorist Views It". Behavioral Development Bulletin. 9 (1): 10–12. doi:10.1037/h0100531. https://psycnet.apa.org/fulltext/2014-55592-003.html
Graham, George (2019). "Behaviorism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 31 May 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/behaviorism/
Mele, Alfred R. (2003). "Introduction". Motivation and Agency. Oxford University Press. https://philpapers.org/rec/MELMAA-2
Mele, Alfred R. (1995). "Motivation: Essentially Motivation-Constituting Attitudes". Philosophical Review. 104 (3): 387–423. doi:10.2307/2185634. JSTOR 2185634. https://philpapers.org/rec/MELMEM
Schwitzgebel, Eric (2019). "Belief". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 15 November 2019. Retrieved 22 June 2020. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/belief/
Borchert, Donald (2006). "Belief". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. Archived from the original on 12 January 2021. Retrieved 2 April 2021. https://philpapers.org/rec/BORMEO
Milkowski, Marcin. "Computational Theory of Mind". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 21 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/compmind/
"Philosophy of mind – The computational-representational theory of thought (CRTT)". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 21 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/philosophy-of-mind/The-computational-representational-theory-of-thought-CRTT
Rescorla, Michael (2020). "The Computational Theory of Mind". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 22 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/computational-mind/
"Philosophy of mind – The computational-representational theory of thought (CRTT)". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 21 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/philosophy-of-mind/The-computational-representational-theory-of-thought-CRTT
"Thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 14 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/thought
Baum, Eric B. (2004). "1. Introduction". What Is Thought?. Cambridge MA: Bradford Book/MIT Press. https://philpapers.org/rec/BAUWIT
Rescorla, Michael (2020). "The Computational Theory of Mind". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 22 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/computational-mind/
Milkowski, Marcin. "Computational Theory of Mind". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 21 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/compmind/
Milkowski, Marcin. "Computational Theory of Mind". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 21 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/compmind/
"Philosophy of mind – The computational-representational theory of thought (CRTT)". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 21 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/philosophy-of-mind/The-computational-representational-theory-of-thought-CRTT
Rescorla, Michael (2020). "The Computational Theory of Mind". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 22 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/computational-mind/
Rescorla, Michael (2020). "The Computational Theory of Mind". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 22 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/computational-mind/
Rescorla, Michael (2020). "The Computational Theory of Mind". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 22 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/computational-mind/
Polger, Thomas W. "Functionalism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 31 May 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/functism/
Gulick, Robert Van (2009). Beckermann, Ansgar; McLaughlin, Brian P; Walter, Sven (eds.). "Functionalism". The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-926261-8. 978-0-19-926261-8
Honderich, Ted (2005). "Mind". The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. https://philpapers.org/rec/HONTOC-2
Levin, Janet (2021). "Functionalism: 2.2 Thinking Machines and the "Turing Test"". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 22 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/functionalism/#ThiMacTurTes
Polger, Thomas W. "Functionalism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 31 May 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/functism/
Pitt, David (2020). "Mental Representation: 1. The Representational Theory of Mind". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 22 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mental-representation/#Representational
Rescorla, Michael (2020). "The Computational Theory of Mind". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 22 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/computational-mind/
Rescorla, Michael (2020). "The Computational Theory of Mind". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 22 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/computational-mind/
Rescorla, Michael (2019). "The Language of Thought Hypothesis". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/language-thought/
Rescorla, Michael (2020). "The Computational Theory of Mind". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 22 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/computational-mind/
Rescorla, Michael (2020). "The Computational Theory of Mind". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 22 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/computational-mind/
"Philosophy of mind – The computational-representational theory of thought (CRTT)". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 21 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/philosophy-of-mind/The-computational-representational-theory-of-thought-CRTT
Borchert, Donald (2006). "Thinking". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. https://philpapers.org/rec/BORMEO
Crowell, Steven (2015). "What Is It to Think?". In Breyer, Thiemo; Gutland, Christopher (eds.). Phenomenology of Thinking. Routledge. pp. 189–212. doi:10.4324/9781315697734. ISBN 978-1-315-69773-4. 978-1-315-69773-4
Schmidt, R. W. "Judgment". New Catholic Encyclopedia. https://www.encyclopedia.com/social-sciences-and-law/law/law/judgment
Sgarbi, Marco (2006). "Theories of Judgment. Historical and Theoretical Perspectives". Quaestio. 6 (1): 589–592. doi:10.1484/J.QUAESTIO.2.302491. https://philpapers.org/rec/SGATOJ
Robins, E. P. (1898). "Modern Theories of Judgment". Philosophical Review. 7 (6): 583–603. doi:10.2307/2176171. JSTOR 2176171. https://philpapers.org/rec/ROBMTO
Rojszczak, Artur; Smith, Barry (2003). "Theories of Judgment". The Cambridge History of Philosophy 1870-1945. Cambridge University Press: 157–173. doi:10.1017/CHOL9780521591041.013. ISBN 978-0521591041. 978-0521591041
Hanna, Robert (2018). "Kant's Theory of Judgment". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 24 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-judgment/
Rojszczak, Artur; Smith, Barry (2003). "Theories of Judgment". The Cambridge History of Philosophy 1870-1945. Cambridge University Press: 157–173. doi:10.1017/CHOL9780521591041.013. ISBN 978-0521591041. 978-0521591041
Brandl, Johannes L.; Textor, Mark (2020). "Brentano's Theory of Judgement". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 24 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/brentano-judgement/
Rojszczak, Artur; Smith, Barry (2003). "Theories of Judgment". The Cambridge History of Philosophy 1870-1945. Cambridge University Press: 157–173. doi:10.1017/CHOL9780521591041.013. ISBN 978-0521591041. 978-0521591041
Brandl, Johannes L.; Textor, Mark (2020). "Brentano's Theory of Judgement". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 24 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/brentano-judgement/
Rojszczak, Artur; Smith, Barry (2003). "Theories of Judgment". The Cambridge History of Philosophy 1870-1945. Cambridge University Press: 157–173. doi:10.1017/CHOL9780521591041.013. ISBN 978-0521591041. 978-0521591041
Brandl, Johannes L.; Textor, Mark (2020). "Brentano's Theory of Judgement". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 24 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/brentano-judgement/
Rojszczak, Artur; Smith, Barry (2003). "Theories of Judgment". The Cambridge History of Philosophy 1870-1945. Cambridge University Press: 157–173. doi:10.1017/CHOL9780521591041.013. ISBN 978-0521591041. 978-0521591041
Brandl, Johannes L.; Textor, Mark (2020). "Brentano's Theory of Judgement". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 24 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/brentano-judgement/
Mandelbaum, Eric (2014). "Thinking is Believing". Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy. 57 (1): 55–96. doi:10.1080/0020174X.2014.858417. S2CID 52968342. https://philpapers.org/rec/MANTIB-2
Crowell, Steven (2015). "What Is It to Think?". In Breyer, Thiemo; Gutland, Christopher (eds.). Phenomenology of Thinking. Routledge. pp. 189–212. doi:10.4324/9781315697734. ISBN 978-1-315-69773-4. 978-1-315-69773-4
"Thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 14 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/thought
Vinacke, W. Edgar. "Thought". International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences. https://www.encyclopedia.com/social-sciences-and-law/sociology-and-social-reform/sociology-general-terms-and-concepts/thinking
Pollock, John L. (1987). "Defeasible Reasoning". Cognitive Science. 11 (4): 481–518. doi:10.1207/s15516709cog1104_4. https://doi.org/10.1207%2Fs15516709cog1104_4
Koons, Robert (2021). "Defeasible Reasoning". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 16 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/reasoning-defeasible/
Hansen, Hans (2020). "Fallacies". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 March 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/fallacies/
Vleet, Van Jacob E. (2010). "Introduction". Informal Logical Fallacies: A Brief Guide. Upa. https://philpapers.org/rec/VLEILF
"Thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 14 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/thought
Stone, Mark A. (2012). "Denying the Antecedent: Its Effective Use in Argumentation". Informal Logic. 32 (3): 327–356. doi:10.22329/il.v32i3.3681. https://philpapers.org/rec/STODTA
Dowden, Bradley. "Fallacies". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 19 March 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/fallacy/
Hansen, Hans (2020). "Fallacies". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 March 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/fallacies/
Walton, Douglas N. (1987). "1. A new model of argument". Informal Fallacies: Towards a Theory of Argument Criticisms. John Benjamins. https://philpapers.org/rec/WALIFT
Engel, S. Morris (1982). "2. The medium of language". With Good Reason an Introduction to Informal Fallacies. St. Martin's Press. https://philpapers.org/rec/ENGWGR
Hansen, Hans (2020). "Fallacies". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 March 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/fallacies/
"Thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 14 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/thought
Margolis, Eric; Laurence, Stephen (2021). "Concepts". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 28 September 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/concepts/
"Philosophy of mind – Thoughts and attitudes". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 16 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/philosophy-of-mind/Thoughts-and-attitudes
"Concept formation". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 16 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/concept-formation
Kazdin, Alan E., ed. (2000). "Thinking: An Overview". Encyclopedia of Psychology. American Psychological Association. ISBN 978-1-55798-187-5. 978-1-55798-187-5
Fodor, Jerry (2004). "Having Concepts: A Brief Refutation of the Twentieth Century". Mind and Language. 19 (1): 29–47. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0017.2004.00245.x. https://philpapers.org/rec/FODHCA
Kazdin, Alan E., ed. (2000). "Thinking: An Overview". Encyclopedia of Psychology. American Psychological Association. ISBN 978-1-55798-187-5. 978-1-55798-187-5
"Concept formation". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 16 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/concept-formation
Kazdin, Alan E., ed. (2000). "Thinking: An Overview". Encyclopedia of Psychology. American Psychological Association. ISBN 978-1-55798-187-5. 978-1-55798-187-5
Margolis, Eric; Laurence, Stephen (2021). "Concepts". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 28 September 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/concepts/
Ortony, Andrew (26 November 1993) [1979]. "Metaphor, language, and thought". In Ortony, Andrew (ed.). Metaphor and Thought (2 ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 2. ISBN 9780521405614. Retrieved 21 February 2024. The constructivist approach seems to entail an important role for metaphor in both language and thought [...].
9780521405614
Fodor, Jerry (2004). "Having Concepts: A Brief Refutation of the Twentieth Century". Mind and Language. 19 (1): 29–47. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0017.2004.00245.x. https://philpapers.org/rec/FODHCA
Weiskopf, Daniel A.; Bechtel, William (2004). "Remarks on Fodor on Having Concepts". Mind and Language. 19 (1): 48–56. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0017.2004.00246.x. https://philpapers.org/rec/WEIROF
Margolis, Eric; Laurence, Stephen (2021). "Concepts". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 28 September 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/concepts/
"Concept formation". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 16 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/concept-formation
"Learning theory". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 16 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/science/learning-theory
Mole, Christopher (2021). "Attention: 2.3 Coherence Theories". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 21 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/attention/#CohThe
"Thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 14 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/thought
Kazdin, Alan E., ed. (2000). "Thinking: An Overview". Encyclopedia of Psychology. American Psychological Association. ISBN 978-1-55798-187-5. 978-1-55798-187-5
"Thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 14 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/thought
Kim, Kyung Hee; Pierce, Robert A. (2013). "Convergent Versus Divergent Thinking". Encyclopedia of Creativity, Invention, Innovation and Entrepreneurship. Springer. pp. 245–250. doi:10.1007/978-1-4614-3858-8_22. ISBN 978-1-4614-3857-1. Retrieved 24 October 2021. 978-1-4614-3857-1
Razumnikova, Olga M. (2013). "Divergent Versus Convergent Thinking". Encyclopedia of Creativity, Invention, Innovation and Entrepreneurship. Springer. pp. 546–552. doi:10.1007/978-1-4614-3858-8_362. ISBN 978-1-4614-3857-1. Retrieved 24 October 2021. 978-1-4614-3857-1
"Thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 14 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/thought
"Thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 14 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/thought
Reed, Stephen K. (1 December 2016). "The Structure of Ill-Structured (and Well-Structured) Problems Revisited". Educational Psychology Review. 28 (4): 691–716. doi:10.1007/s10648-015-9343-1. ISSN 1573-336X. S2CID 146496245. https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s10648-015-9343-1
"Thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 14 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/thought
Reed, Stephen K. (1 December 2016). "The Structure of Ill-Structured (and Well-Structured) Problems Revisited". Educational Psychology Review. 28 (4): 691–716. doi:10.1007/s10648-015-9343-1. ISSN 1573-336X. S2CID 146496245. https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s10648-015-9343-1
Kazdin, Alan E., ed. (2000). "Thinking: An Overview". Encyclopedia of Psychology. American Psychological Association. ISBN 978-1-55798-187-5. 978-1-55798-187-5
"Thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 14 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/thought
Kazdin, Alan E., ed. (2000). "Thinking: An Overview". Encyclopedia of Psychology. American Psychological Association. ISBN 978-1-55798-187-5. 978-1-55798-187-5
"Thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 14 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/thought
Kazdin, Alan E., ed. (2000). "Thinking: An Overview". Encyclopedia of Psychology. American Psychological Association. ISBN 978-1-55798-187-5. 978-1-55798-187-5
"Thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 14 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/thought
"Thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 14 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/thought
"Thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 14 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/thought
Arpaly, N.; Schroeder, T. (2012). "Deliberation and Acting for Reasons". Philosophical Review. 121 (2): 209–239. doi:10.1215/00318108-1539089. https://philpapers.org/rec/ARPDAA
Vinacke, W. Edgar. "Thought". International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences. https://www.encyclopedia.com/social-sciences-and-law/sociology-and-social-reform/sociology-general-terms-and-concepts/thinking
Borchert, Donald (2006). "Thinking". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. https://philpapers.org/rec/BORMEO
Kazdin, Alan E., ed. (2000). "Thinking: An Overview". Encyclopedia of Psychology. American Psychological Association. ISBN 978-1-55798-187-5. 978-1-55798-187-5
Steele, Katie; Stefánsson, H. Orri (2020). "Decision Theory". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 24 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/decision-theory/
Buchak, Lara (2016). "Decision Theory". The Oxford Handbook of Probability and Philosophy. Oxford University Press. /wiki/Lara_Buchak
Steele, Katie; Stefánsson, H. Orri (2020). "Decision Theory". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 24 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/decision-theory/
Buchak, Lara (2016). "Decision Theory". The Oxford Handbook of Probability and Philosophy. Oxford University Press. /wiki/Lara_Buchak
Steele, Katie; Stefánsson, H. Orri (2020). "Decision Theory". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 24 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/decision-theory/
Buchak, Lara (2016). "Decision Theory". The Oxford Handbook of Probability and Philosophy. Oxford University Press. /wiki/Lara_Buchak
"Thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 14 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/thought
"Thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 14 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/thought
"The American Heritage Dictionary entry: think". www.ahdictionary.com. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing. Retrieved 23 October 2021. https://www.ahdictionary.com/word/search.html?q=think
Perrin, Denis; Michaelian, Kourken; Sant’Anna, André (2020). "The Phenomenology of Remembering Is an Epistemic Feeling". Frontiers in Psychology. 11: 1531. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2020.01531. ISSN 1664-1078. PMC 7350950. PMID 32719642. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC7350950
Gardiner, J. M. (29 September 2001). "Episodic memory and autonoetic consciousness: a first-person approach". Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B, Biological Sciences. 356 (1413): 1351–1361. doi:10.1098/rstb.2001.0955. ISSN 0962-8436. PMC 1088519. PMID 11571027. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC1088519
Michaelian, Kourken; Sutton, John (2017). "Memory: 3. Episodicity". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 2 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/memory/#Epis
Michaelian, Kourken; Sutton, John (2017). "Memory: 3. Episodicity". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 2 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/memory/#Epis
Tulving, Endel. "Learning and Memory: Episodic Memory". https://www.encyclopedia.com/psychology/encyclopedias-almanacs-transcripts-and-maps/episodic-memory
Perrin, Denis; Michaelian, Kourken; Sant’Anna, André (2020). "The Phenomenology of Remembering Is an Epistemic Feeling". Frontiers in Psychology. 11: 1531. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2020.01531. ISSN 1664-1078. PMC 7350950. PMID 32719642. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC7350950
Michaelian, Kourken; Sutton, John (2017). "Memory: 3. Episodicity". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 2 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/memory/#Epis
Michaelian, Kourken; Sutton, John (2017). "Memory: 4. Mnemicity". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 2 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/memory/#Mnem
Manser, A. R. "Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Imagination". Retrieved 3 October 2021. https://www.encyclopedia.com/medicine/psychology/psychology-and-psychiatry/imagination
Russell, Bertrand (1915). "Sensation and Imagination". The Monist. 25 (1): 28–44. doi:10.5840/monist191525136. https://philpapers.org/rec/RUSSAI
Manser, A. R. "Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Imagination". Retrieved 3 October 2021. https://www.encyclopedia.com/medicine/psychology/psychology-and-psychiatry/imagination
Garrison, Katie E.; Handley, Ian M. (2017). "Not Merely Experiential: Unconscious Thought Can Be Rational". Frontiers in Psychology. 8: 1096. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2017.01096. ISSN 1664-1078. PMC 5498519. PMID 28729844. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC5498519
Dijksterhuis, Ap; Nordgren, Loran F. (1 June 2006). "A Theory of Unconscious Thought". Perspectives on Psychological Science. 1 (2): 95–109. doi:10.1111/j.1745-6916.2006.00007.x. hdl:2066/55863. ISSN 1745-6916. PMID 26151465. S2CID 7875280. https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/10.1111/j.1745-6916.2006.00007.x
Breyer, Thiemo; Gutland, Christopher (2015). "Introduction". Phenomenology of Thinking: Philosophical Investigations into the Character of Cognitive Experiences. Routledge. pp. 1–24. https://philpapers.org/rec/BREI-15
Nida-rümelin, Martine (2010). "Thinking Without Language. A Phenomenological Argument for Its Possibility and Existence". Grazer Philosophische Studien. 81 (1): 55–75. doi:10.1163/9789042030190_005. https://philpapers.org/rec/NIDTWL
Dijksterhuis, Ap; Nordgren, Loran F. (1 June 2006). "A Theory of Unconscious Thought". Perspectives on Psychological Science. 1 (2): 95–109. doi:10.1111/j.1745-6916.2006.00007.x. hdl:2066/55863. ISSN 1745-6916. PMID 26151465. S2CID 7875280. https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/10.1111/j.1745-6916.2006.00007.x
Dijksterhuis, Ap; Nordgren, Loran F. (1 June 2006). "A Theory of Unconscious Thought". Perspectives on Psychological Science. 1 (2): 95–109. doi:10.1111/j.1745-6916.2006.00007.x. hdl:2066/55863. ISSN 1745-6916. PMID 26151465. S2CID 7875280. https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/10.1111/j.1745-6916.2006.00007.x
Garrison, Katie E.; Handley, Ian M. (2017). "Not Merely Experiential: Unconscious Thought Can Be Rational". Frontiers in Psychology. 8: 1096. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2017.01096. ISSN 1664-1078. PMC 5498519. PMID 28729844. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC5498519
Dijksterhuis, Ap; Nordgren, Loran F. (1 June 2006). "A Theory of Unconscious Thought". Perspectives on Psychological Science. 1 (2): 95–109. doi:10.1111/j.1745-6916.2006.00007.x. hdl:2066/55863. ISSN 1745-6916. PMID 26151465. S2CID 7875280. https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/10.1111/j.1745-6916.2006.00007.x
Garrison, Katie E.; Handley, Ian M. (2017). "Not Merely Experiential: Unconscious Thought Can Be Rational". Frontiers in Psychology. 8: 1096. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2017.01096. ISSN 1664-1078. PMC 5498519. PMID 28729844. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC5498519
Dijksterhuis, Ap; Nordgren, Loran F. (1 June 2006). "A Theory of Unconscious Thought". Perspectives on Psychological Science. 1 (2): 95–109. doi:10.1111/j.1745-6916.2006.00007.x. hdl:2066/55863. ISSN 1745-6916. PMID 26151465. S2CID 7875280. https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/10.1111/j.1745-6916.2006.00007.x
Garrison, Katie E.; Handley, Ian M. (2017). "Not Merely Experiential: Unconscious Thought Can Be Rational". Frontiers in Psychology. 8: 1096. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2017.01096. ISSN 1664-1078. PMC 5498519. PMID 28729844. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC5498519
Dijksterhuis, Ap; Nordgren, Loran F. (1 June 2006). "A Theory of Unconscious Thought". Perspectives on Psychological Science. 1 (2): 95–109. doi:10.1111/j.1745-6916.2006.00007.x. hdl:2066/55863. ISSN 1745-6916. PMID 26151465. S2CID 7875280. https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/10.1111/j.1745-6916.2006.00007.x
Abbott, Alison (1 January 2015). "Unconscious thought not so smart after all". Nature. 517 (7536): 537–538. Bibcode:2015Natur.517..537A. doi:10.1038/517537a. ISSN 1476-4687. PMID 25631423. /wiki/Bibcode_(identifier)
Mealor, Andy David; Dienes, Zoltan (2012). "Conscious and Unconscious Thought in Artificial Grammar Learning". Consciousness and Cognition. 21 (2): 865–874. doi:10.1016/j.concog.2012.03.001. PMID 22472202. S2CID 40114660. https://philpapers.org/rec/MEACAU
Dijksterhuis, Ap; Nordgren, Loran F. (1 June 2006). "A Theory of Unconscious Thought". Perspectives on Psychological Science. 1 (2): 95–109. doi:10.1111/j.1745-6916.2006.00007.x. hdl:2066/55863. ISSN 1745-6916. PMID 26151465. S2CID 7875280. https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/10.1111/j.1745-6916.2006.00007.x
Fowles, Christopher (2 January 2019). "Nietzsche on conscious and unconscious thought". Inquiry. 62 (1): 1–22. doi:10.1080/0020174X.2019.1527537. ISSN 0020-174X. S2CID 171812391. https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/abs/10.1080/0020174X.2019.1527537?journalCode=sinq20
Smith, David Woodruff (2018). "Phenomenology: 1. What is Phenomenology?". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 20 September 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/phenomenology/#WhatPhen
Smith, Joel. "Phenomenology". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 10 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/phenom/
Breyer, Thiemo; Gutland, Christopher (2015). "Introduction". Phenomenology of Thinking: Philosophical Investigations into the Character of Cognitive Experiences. Routledge. pp. 1–24. https://philpapers.org/rec/BREI-15
Hansen, Mette Kristine. "Cognitive Phenomenology". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 17 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/cog-phen/
Kriegel, Uriah (2015). "The Character of Cognitive Phenomenology". Phenomenology of Thinking. London and New York: Routledge. pp. 25–43. https://philpapers.org/rec/KRITCO-10
Crowell, Steven (2015). "What Is It to Think?". In Breyer, Thiemo; Gutland, Christopher (eds.). Phenomenology of Thinking. Routledge. pp. 189–212. doi:10.4324/9781315697734. ISBN 978-1-315-69773-4. 978-1-315-69773-4
Carruthers, Peter; Veillet, Bénédicte (2011). "The Case Against Cognitive Phenomenology". Cognitive Phenomenology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-957993-8. 978-0-19-957993-8
Carruthers, Peter; Veillet, Bénédicte (2011). "The Case Against Cognitive Phenomenology". Cognitive Phenomenology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-957993-8. 978-0-19-957993-8
Prinz, Jesse J. (2011). "The Sensory Basis of Cognitive Phenomenology 1". Cognitive Phenomenology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-957993-8. 978-0-19-957993-8
Levine, Joseph (2011). "On the Phenomenology of Thought". Cognitive Phenomenology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-957993-8. 978-0-19-957993-8
Prinz, Jesse J. (2011). "The Sensory Basis of Cognitive Phenomenology 1". Cognitive Phenomenology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-957993-8. 978-0-19-957993-8
Breyer, Thiemo; Gutland, Christopher (2015). "Introduction". Phenomenology of Thinking: Philosophical Investigations into the Character of Cognitive Experiences. Routledge. pp. 1–24. https://philpapers.org/rec/BREI-15
Hansen, Mette Kristine. "Cognitive Phenomenology". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 17 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/cog-phen/
Breyer, Thiemo; Gutland, Christopher (2015). "Introduction". Phenomenology of Thinking: Philosophical Investigations into the Character of Cognitive Experiences. Routledge. pp. 1–24. https://philpapers.org/rec/BREI-15
Prinz, Jesse J. (2011). "The Sensory Basis of Cognitive Phenomenology 1". Cognitive Phenomenology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-957993-8. 978-0-19-957993-8
Levine, Joseph (2011). "On the Phenomenology of Thought". Cognitive Phenomenology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-957993-8. 978-0-19-957993-8
Breyer, Thiemo; Gutland, Christopher (2015). "Introduction". Phenomenology of Thinking: Philosophical Investigations into the Character of Cognitive Experiences. Routledge. pp. 1–24. https://philpapers.org/rec/BREI-15
Hansen, Mette Kristine. "Cognitive Phenomenology". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 17 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/cog-phen/
Kriegel, Uriah (2015). "The Character of Cognitive Phenomenology". Phenomenology of Thinking. London and New York: Routledge. pp. 25–43. https://philpapers.org/rec/KRITCO-10
Siewert, Charles (2011). "Phenomenal Thought". Cognitive Phenomenology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-957993-8. 978-0-19-957993-8
Breyer, Thiemo; Gutland, Christopher (2015). "Introduction". Phenomenology of Thinking: Philosophical Investigations into the Character of Cognitive Experiences. Routledge. pp. 1–24. https://philpapers.org/rec/BREI-15
Hansen, Mette Kristine. "Cognitive Phenomenology". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 17 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/cog-phen/
Kriegel, Uriah (2015). "The Character of Cognitive Phenomenology". Phenomenology of Thinking. London and New York: Routledge. pp. 25–43. https://philpapers.org/rec/KRITCO-10
Pitt, David (2004). "The Phenomenology of Cognition: Or What Is It Like to Think That P?". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 69 (1): 1–36. doi:10.1111/j.1933-1592.2004.tb00382.x. https://philpapers.org/rec/PITWII
Breyer, Thiemo; Gutland, Christopher (2015). "Introduction". Phenomenology of Thinking: Philosophical Investigations into the Character of Cognitive Experiences. Routledge. pp. 1–24. https://philpapers.org/rec/BREI-15
Hansen, Mette Kristine. "Cognitive Phenomenology". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 17 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/cog-phen/
Kriegel, Uriah (2015). "The Character of Cognitive Phenomenology". Phenomenology of Thinking. London and New York: Routledge. pp. 25–43. https://philpapers.org/rec/KRITCO-10
Kriegel, Uriah (2015). "The Character of Cognitive Phenomenology". Phenomenology of Thinking. London and New York: Routledge. pp. 25–43. https://philpapers.org/rec/KRITCO-10
Smith, David Woodruff (2011). "The Phenomenology of Consciously Thinking". Cognitive Phenomenology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-957993-8. 978-0-19-957993-8
Kriegel, Uriah (2015). "The Character of Cognitive Phenomenology". Phenomenology of Thinking. London and New York: Routledge. pp. 25–43. https://philpapers.org/rec/KRITCO-10
Crowell, Steven (2015). "What Is It to Think?". In Breyer, Thiemo; Gutland, Christopher (eds.). Phenomenology of Thinking. Routledge. pp. 189–212. doi:10.4324/9781315697734. ISBN 978-1-315-69773-4. 978-1-315-69773-4
Hansen, Mette Kristine. "Cognitive Phenomenology". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 17 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/cog-phen/
Crowell, Steven (2015). "What Is It to Think?". In Breyer, Thiemo; Gutland, Christopher (eds.). Phenomenology of Thinking. Routledge. pp. 189–212. doi:10.4324/9781315697734. ISBN 978-1-315-69773-4. 978-1-315-69773-4
Dastur, Françoise; Vallier, Robert (2017). "The Problem of Pre-Predicative Experience: Husserl". Questions of Phenomenology. Fordham University Press. doi:10.5422/fordham/9780823233731.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-8232-3373-1. S2CID 148619048. 978-0-8232-3373-1
Staiti, Andrea (2018). Zahavi, Dan (ed.). Pre-Predicative Experience and Life-World. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780198755340.013.12. ISBN 978-0-19-875534-0. 978-0-19-875534-0
Breyer, Thiemo; Gutland, Christopher (2015). "Introduction". Phenomenology of Thinking: Philosophical Investigations into the Character of Cognitive Experiences. Routledge. pp. 1–24. https://philpapers.org/rec/BREI-15
Diaz, Emiliano (2020). "Transcendental Anticipation: A Reconsideration of Husserl's Type and Kant's Schemata". Husserl Studies. 36 (1): 1–23. doi:10.1007/s10743-019-09249-3. S2CID 203547989. https://philpapers.org/rec/DIATAA-4
Doyon, Maxime (2015). "The "As-Structure" of Intentional Experience in Husserl and Heidegger". Phenomenology of Thinking. Routledge. pp. 122–139. doi:10.4324/9781315697734-10. ISBN 978-1-315-69773-4. 978-1-315-69773-4
Breyer, Thiemo; Gutland, Christopher (2015). "Introduction". Phenomenology of Thinking: Philosophical Investigations into the Character of Cognitive Experiences. Routledge. pp. 1–24. https://philpapers.org/rec/BREI-15
Diaz, Emiliano (2020). "Transcendental Anticipation: A Reconsideration of Husserl's Type and Kant's Schemata". Husserl Studies. 36 (1): 1–23. doi:10.1007/s10743-019-09249-3. S2CID 203547989. https://philpapers.org/rec/DIATAA-4
Breyer, Thiemo; Gutland, Christopher (2015). "Introduction". Phenomenology of Thinking: Philosophical Investigations into the Character of Cognitive Experiences. Routledge. pp. 1–24. https://philpapers.org/rec/BREI-15
Breyer, Thiemo; Gutland, Christopher (2015). "Introduction". Phenomenology of Thinking: Philosophical Investigations into the Character of Cognitive Experiences. Routledge. pp. 1–24. https://philpapers.org/rec/BREI-15
Breyer, Thiemo; Gutland, Christopher (2015). "Introduction". Phenomenology of Thinking: Philosophical Investigations into the Character of Cognitive Experiences. Routledge. pp. 1–24. https://philpapers.org/rec/BREI-15
Doyon, Maxime (2015). "The "As-Structure" of Intentional Experience in Husserl and Heidegger". Phenomenology of Thinking. Routledge. pp. 122–139. doi:10.4324/9781315697734-10. ISBN 978-1-315-69773-4. 978-1-315-69773-4
Dastur, Françoise; Vallier, Robert (2017). "The Problem of Pre-Predicative Experience: Husserl". Questions of Phenomenology. Fordham University Press. doi:10.5422/fordham/9780823233731.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-8232-3373-1. S2CID 148619048. 978-0-8232-3373-1
Staiti, Andrea (2018). Zahavi, Dan (ed.). Pre-Predicative Experience and Life-World. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780198755340.013.12. ISBN 978-0-19-875534-0. 978-0-19-875534-0
Hopp, Walter (2015). "Empty Intentions and Phenomenological Character: A Defense of Inclusivism". Phenomenology of Thinking. Routledge. pp. 50–67. doi:10.4324/9781315697734-6. ISBN 978-1-315-69773-4. 978-1-315-69773-4
Spear, Andrew D. "Husserl, Edmund: Intentionality and Intentional Content: 2ai Act-Character". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 26 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/huss-int/#SSH2ai
Hopp, Walter (2015). "Empty Intentions and Phenomenological Character: A Defense of Inclusivism". Phenomenology of Thinking. Routledge. pp. 50–67. doi:10.4324/9781315697734-6. ISBN 978-1-315-69773-4. 978-1-315-69773-4
Breyer, Thiemo; Gutland, Christopher (2015). "Introduction". Phenomenology of Thinking: Philosophical Investigations into the Character of Cognitive Experiences. Routledge. pp. 1–24. https://philpapers.org/rec/BREI-15
Spear, Andrew D. "Husserl, Edmund: Intentionality and Intentional Content: 2ai Act-Character". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 26 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/huss-int/#SSH2ai
Spear, Andrew D. "Husserl, Edmund: Intentionality and Intentional Content: 2ai Act-Character". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 26 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/huss-int/#SSH2ai
Hopp, Walter (2015). "Empty Intentions and Phenomenological Character: A Defense of Inclusivism". Phenomenology of Thinking. Routledge. pp. 50–67. doi:10.4324/9781315697734-6. ISBN 978-1-315-69773-4. 978-1-315-69773-4
Crowell, Steven (2015). "What Is It to Think?". In Breyer, Thiemo; Gutland, Christopher (eds.). Phenomenology of Thinking. Routledge. pp. 189–212. doi:10.4324/9781315697734. ISBN 978-1-315-69773-4. 978-1-315-69773-4
Crowell, Steven (2015). "What Is It to Think?". In Breyer, Thiemo; Gutland, Christopher (eds.). Phenomenology of Thinking. Routledge. pp. 189–212. doi:10.4324/9781315697734. ISBN 978-1-315-69773-4. 978-1-315-69773-4
Spear, Andrew D. "Husserl, Edmund: Intentionality and Intentional Content: 2ai Act-Character". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 26 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/huss-int/#SSH2ai
Kim, J. (1995). Honderich, Ted (ed.). Problems in the Philosophy of Mind. Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-866132-0. 978-0-19-866132-0
Companion to Metaphysics, By Jaegwon Kim, Gary S. Rosenkrantz, Ernest Sosa, Contributor Jaegwon Kim, 2nd ed., Wiley-Blackwell, 2009, ISBN 978-1-4051-5298-3 /wiki/Gary_S._Rosenkrantz
Varela, Francisco J., Thompson, Evan T., and Rosch, Eleanor. (1992). The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. ISBN 0-262-72021-3 /wiki/ISBN_(identifier)
Cowart, Monica (2004). "Embodied Cognition". The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. ISSN 2161-0002. Retrieved 27 February 2012. http://www.iep.utm.edu/embodcog/
Di Paolo, Ezequiel (2009). "Shallow and Deep Embodiment" (Video, duration: 1:11:38). University of Sussex. Retrieved 27 February 2012. https://cast.switch.ch/vod/clips/74nrkbwys
Gestalt Theory, By Max Wertheimer. Hayes Barton Press, 1944, ISBN 978-1-59377-695-4 /wiki/ISBN_(identifier)
Piaget, J. (1951). Psychology of Intelligence. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul
Demetriou, A. (1998). Cognitive development. In A. Demetriou, W. Doise, K. F. M. van Lieshout (Eds.), Life-span developmental psychology. pp. 179–269. London: Wiley.
Schacter, Daniel L. (2011). "Positive Psychology". Psychology (Second ed.). New York: Worth. 584 pp.
Snowden, Ruth (2006). Teach Yourself Freud (illustrated ed.). McGraw-Hill. p. 107. ISBN 978-0-07-147274-6. 978-0-07-147274-6
The Cambridge companion to Freud, By Jerome Neu. Cambridge University Press, 1991, p. 29, ISBN 978-0-521-37779-9 /wiki/ISBN_(identifier)
Jensen, Peter S., Mrazek, David, Knapp, Penelope K., Steinberg, Laurence, Pfeffer, Cynthia, Schowalter, John, & Shapiro, Theodore. (Dec 1997) "Evolution and revolution in child psychiatry: ADHD as a disorder of adaptation. (attention-deficit hyperactivity syndrome)". Journal of the American Academy of Child and Adolescent Psychiatry. 36. p. 1672. (10). July 14, 2007. /wiki/Laurence_Steinberg
"Laws of thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 28 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/laws-of-thought
Borchert, Donald (2006). "Laws of Thought". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. https://philpapers.org/rec/BORMEO
"Laws of thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 28 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/laws-of-thought
Borchert, Donald (2006). "Laws of Thought". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. https://philpapers.org/rec/BORMEO
Borchert, Donald (2006). "Laws of Thought". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. https://philpapers.org/rec/BORMEO
Borchert, Donald (2006). "Laws of Thought". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. https://philpapers.org/rec/BORMEO
"Laws of thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 28 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/laws-of-thought
Borchert, Donald (2006). "Laws of Thought". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. https://philpapers.org/rec/BORMEO
"Laws of thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 28 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/laws-of-thought
Borchert, Donald (2006). "Laws of Thought". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. https://philpapers.org/rec/BORMEO
Moschovakis, Joan (2021). "Intuitionistic Logic: 1. Rejection of Tertium Non Datur". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 28 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-intuitionistic/#RejTerNonDat
McKubre-Jordens, Maarten. "Constructive Mathematics: 1b Constructivism as Philosophy". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 28 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/con-math/#SH1b
"Laws of thought". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 28 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/laws-of-thought
Borchert, Donald (2006). "Laws of Thought". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. https://philpapers.org/rec/BORMEO
Priest, Graham; Berto, Francesco; Weber, Zach (2018). "Dialetheism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/dialetheism/
Horn, Laurence R. (2018). "Contradiction". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/contradiction/
Weber, Zach. "Dialetheism". Oxford Bibliographies. Retrieved 28 October 2021. https://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/view/document/obo-9780195396577/obo-9780195396577-0310.xml
Borchert, Donald (2006). "Laws of Thought". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. https://philpapers.org/rec/BORMEO
"principle of sufficient reason". Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 28 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/principle-of-sufficient-reason
Melamed, Yitzhak Y.; Lin, Martin (2021). "Principle of Sufficient Reason". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 28 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/sufficient-reason/
Melamed, Yitzhak Y.; Lin, Martin (2021). "Principle of Sufficient Reason". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 28 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/sufficient-reason/
Borchert, Donald (2006). "Laws of Thought". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. https://philpapers.org/rec/BORMEO
"principle of sufficient reason". Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 28 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/principle-of-sufficient-reason
Roese, Neal J. (1997). "Counterfactual thinking". Psychological Bulletin. 121 (1): 133–148. doi:10.1037/0033-2909.121.1.133. PMID 9000895. https://psycnet.apa.org/record/1997-02112-007
Kazdin, Alan E., ed. (2000). "Counterfactual thought". Encyclopedia of Psychology. American Psychological Association. ISBN 978-1-55798-187-5. 978-1-55798-187-5
Van Hoeck, Nicole; Watson, Patrick D.; Barbey, Aron K. (2015). "Cognitive neuroscience of human counterfactual reasoning". Frontiers in Human Neuroscience. 9: 420. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2015.00420. ISSN 1662-5161. PMC 4511878. PMID 26257633. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC4511878
Starr, William (2021). "Counterfactuals: 1.1 What are Counterfactuals?". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 28 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/counterfactuals/#WhatCoun
Kazdin, Alan E., ed. (2000). "Counterfactual thought". Encyclopedia of Psychology. American Psychological Association. ISBN 978-1-55798-187-5. 978-1-55798-187-5
Roese, Neal J. (1997). "Counterfactual thinking". Psychological Bulletin. 121 (1): 133–148. doi:10.1037/0033-2909.121.1.133. PMID 9000895. https://psycnet.apa.org/record/1997-02112-007
Starr, William (2021). "Counterfactuals: 1.1 What are Counterfactuals?". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 28 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/counterfactuals/#WhatCoun
Van Hoeck, Nicole; Watson, Patrick D.; Barbey, Aron K. (2015). "Cognitive neuroscience of human counterfactual reasoning". Frontiers in Human Neuroscience. 9: 420. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2015.00420. ISSN 1662-5161. PMC 4511878. PMID 26257633. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC4511878
Starr, William (2021). "Counterfactuals: 1.1 What are Counterfactuals?". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 28 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/counterfactuals/#WhatCoun
Roese, Neal J. (1997). "Counterfactual thinking". Psychological Bulletin. 121 (1): 133–148. doi:10.1037/0033-2909.121.1.133. PMID 9000895. https://psycnet.apa.org/record/1997-02112-007
Kazdin, Alan E., ed. (2000). "Counterfactual thought". Encyclopedia of Psychology. American Psychological Association. ISBN 978-1-55798-187-5. 978-1-55798-187-5
Van Hoeck, Nicole; Watson, Patrick D.; Barbey, Aron K. (2015). "Cognitive neuroscience of human counterfactual reasoning". Frontiers in Human Neuroscience. 9: 420. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2015.00420. ISSN 1662-5161. PMC 4511878. PMID 26257633. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC4511878
Roese, Neal J. (1997). "Counterfactual thinking". Psychological Bulletin. 121 (1): 133–148. doi:10.1037/0033-2909.121.1.133. PMID 9000895. https://psycnet.apa.org/record/1997-02112-007
Kazdin, Alan E., ed. (2000). "Counterfactual thought". Encyclopedia of Psychology. American Psychological Association. ISBN 978-1-55798-187-5. 978-1-55798-187-5
Van Hoeck, Nicole; Watson, Patrick D.; Barbey, Aron K. (2015). "Cognitive neuroscience of human counterfactual reasoning". Frontiers in Human Neuroscience. 9: 420. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2015.00420. ISSN 1662-5161. PMC 4511878. PMID 26257633. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC4511878
Roese, Neal J. (1997). "Counterfactual thinking". Psychological Bulletin. 121 (1): 133–148. doi:10.1037/0033-2909.121.1.133. PMID 9000895. https://psycnet.apa.org/record/1997-02112-007
Kazdin, Alan E., ed. (2000). "Counterfactual thought". Encyclopedia of Psychology. American Psychological Association. ISBN 978-1-55798-187-5. 978-1-55798-187-5
Kazdin, Alan E., ed. (2000). "Counterfactual thought". Encyclopedia of Psychology. American Psychological Association. ISBN 978-1-55798-187-5. 978-1-55798-187-5
Roese, Neal J. (1997). "Counterfactual thinking". Psychological Bulletin. 121 (1): 133–148. doi:10.1037/0033-2909.121.1.133. PMID 9000895. https://psycnet.apa.org/record/1997-02112-007
"The American Heritage Dictionary entry: thought experiment". www.ahdictionary.com. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing. Retrieved 30 October 2021. https://www.ahdictionary.com/word/search.html?q=thought+experiment
Brown, James Robert; Fehige, Yiftach (2019). "Thought Experiments". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 29 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/thought-experiment/
Goffi, Jean-Yves; Roux, Sophie (2011). "On the Very Idea of a Thought Experiment". Thought Experiments in Methodological and Historical Contexts. Brill: 165–191. doi:10.1163/ej.9789004201767.i-233.35. ISBN 978-9004201774. S2CID 260640180. 978-9004201774
Sorensen, Roy A. (1999). "Are Thought Experiments Experiments?". Thought Experiments. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/019512913X.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-512913-7. 978-0-19-512913-7
Bishop, Michael A. (1999). "Why Thought Experiments Are Not Arguments". Philosophy of Science. 66 (4): 534–541. doi:10.1086/392753. S2CID 170519663. https://philpapers.org/rec/BISWTE
Norton, John D. (1996). "Are Thought Experiments Just What You Thought?". Canadian Journal of Philosophy. 26 (3): 333–366. doi:10.1080/00455091.1996.10717457. S2CID 143017404. https://philpapers.org/rec/NORATE
Sorensen, Roy (1 January 1995). "Roy Sorensen's Thought Experiments". Informal Logic. 17 (3). doi:10.22329/il.v17i3.2425. ISSN 2293-734X. https://informallogic.ca/index.php/informal_logic/article/view/2425/
Sorensen, Roy A. (1999). "Are Thought Experiments Experiments?". Thought Experiments. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/019512913X.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-512913-7. 978-0-19-512913-7
Reiss, Julian (1 December 2009). "Counterfactuals, Thought Experiments, and Singular Causal Analysis in History". Philosophy of Science. 76 (5): 712–723. doi:10.1086/605826. ISSN 0031-8248. S2CID 43496954. https://www.journals.uchicago.edu/doi/abs/10.1086/605826?journalCode=phos
Brown, James Robert; Fehige, Yiftach (2019). "Thought Experiments". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 29 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/thought-experiment/
Sorensen, Roy A. (1999). "Are Thought Experiments Experiments?". Thought Experiments. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/019512913X.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-512913-7. 978-0-19-512913-7
Goffi, Jean-Yves; Roux, Sophie (2011). "On the Very Idea of a Thought Experiment". Thought Experiments in Methodological and Historical Contexts. Brill: 165–191. doi:10.1163/ej.9789004201767.i-233.35. ISBN 978-9004201774. S2CID 260640180. 978-9004201774
Aligica, Paul Dragos; Evans, Anthony J. (1 September 2009). "Thought experiments, counterfactuals and comparative analysis". The Review of Austrian Economics. 22 (3): 225–239. doi:10.1007/s11138-009-0082-8. ISSN 1573-7128. S2CID 144831020. https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s11138-009-0082-8
Cole, David (2020). "The Chinese Room Argument". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 29 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/chinese-room/
Hauser, Larry. "Chinese Room Argument". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 29 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/chineser/
Cole, David (2020). "The Chinese Room Argument". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 29 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/chinese-room/
Hauser, Larry. "Chinese Room Argument". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 29 October 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/chineser/
Brown, James Robert; Fehige, Yiftach (2019). "Thought Experiments". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 29 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/thought-experiment/
Norton, John D. (1996). "Are Thought Experiments Just What You Thought?". Canadian Journal of Philosophy. 26 (3): 333–366. doi:10.1080/00455091.1996.10717457. S2CID 143017404. https://philpapers.org/rec/NORATE
Bishop, Michael A. (1999). "Why Thought Experiments Are Not Arguments". Philosophy of Science. 66 (4): 534–541. doi:10.1086/392753. S2CID 170519663. https://philpapers.org/rec/BISWTE
Sorensen, Roy A. (1999). "Are Thought Experiments Experiments?". Thought Experiments. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/019512913X.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-512913-7. 978-0-19-512913-7
Brown, James Robert; Fehige, Yiftach (2019). "Thought Experiments". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 29 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/thought-experiment/
Norton, John D. (1996). "Are Thought Experiments Just What You Thought?". Canadian Journal of Philosophy. 26 (3): 333–366. doi:10.1080/00455091.1996.10717457. S2CID 143017404. https://philpapers.org/rec/NORATE
Bishop, Michael A. (1999). "Why Thought Experiments Are Not Arguments". Philosophy of Science. 66 (4): 534–541. doi:10.1086/392753. S2CID 170519663. https://philpapers.org/rec/BISWTE
Sorensen, Roy A. (1999). "Are Thought Experiments Experiments?". Thought Experiments. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/019512913X.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-512913-7. 978-0-19-512913-7
Brown, James Robert; Fehige, Yiftach (2019). "Thought Experiments". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 29 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/thought-experiment/
Sorensen, Roy A. (1999). "Are Thought Experiments Experiments?". Thought Experiments. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/019512913X.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-512913-7. 978-0-19-512913-7
Brown, James Robert; Fehige, Yiftach (2019). "Thought Experiments". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 29 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/thought-experiment/
Goffi, Jean-Yves; Roux, Sophie (2011). "On the Very Idea of a Thought Experiment". Thought Experiments in Methodological and Historical Contexts. Brill: 165–191. doi:10.1163/ej.9789004201767.i-233.35. ISBN 978-9004201774. S2CID 260640180. 978-9004201774
Brown, James Robert; Fehige, Yiftach (2019). "Thought Experiments". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 29 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/thought-experiment/
Goffi, Jean-Yves; Roux, Sophie (2011). "On the Very Idea of a Thought Experiment". Thought Experiments in Methodological and Historical Contexts. Brill: 165–191. doi:10.1163/ej.9789004201767.i-233.35. ISBN 978-9004201774. S2CID 260640180. 978-9004201774
Brown, James Robert; Fehige, Yiftach (2019). "Thought Experiments". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 29 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/thought-experiment/
Ennis, Robert H. (2015). "Critical Thinking: A Streamlined Conception". The Palgrave Handbook of Critical Thinking in Higher Education. Palgrave Macmillan US. pp. 31–47. doi:10.1057/9781137378057_2. ISBN 978-1-137-37805-7. 978-1-137-37805-7
Davies, Martin; Barnett, Ronald (2015). "Introduction". The Palgrave Handbook of Critical Thinking in Higher Education. Palgrave Macmillan US. pp. 1–25. doi:10.1057/9781137378057_1. ISBN 978-1-137-37805-7. 978-1-137-37805-7
Hitchcock, David (2020). "Critical Thinking". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 1 November 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/critical-thinking/
Davies, Martin; Barnett, Ronald (2015). "Introduction". The Palgrave Handbook of Critical Thinking in Higher Education. Palgrave Macmillan US. pp. 1–25. doi:10.1057/9781137378057_1. ISBN 978-1-137-37805-7. 978-1-137-37805-7
Davies, Martin; Barnett, Ronald (2015). "Introduction". The Palgrave Handbook of Critical Thinking in Higher Education. Palgrave Macmillan US. pp. 1–25. doi:10.1057/9781137378057_1. ISBN 978-1-137-37805-7. 978-1-137-37805-7
Davies, Martin; Barnett, Ronald (2015). "Introduction". The Palgrave Handbook of Critical Thinking in Higher Education. Palgrave Macmillan US. pp. 1–25. doi:10.1057/9781137378057_1. ISBN 978-1-137-37805-7. 978-1-137-37805-7
Engel, S. Morris (1982). "2. The medium of language". With Good Reason an Introduction to Informal Fallacies. St. Martin's Press. https://philpapers.org/rec/ENGWGR
Walton, Douglas N. (1987). "1. A new model of argument". Informal Fallacies: Towards a Theory of Argument Criticisms. John Benjamins. https://philpapers.org/rec/WALIFT
Hitchcock, David (2020). "Critical Thinking". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 1 November 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/critical-thinking/
Hitchcock, David (2020). "Critical Thinking". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 1 November 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/critical-thinking/
Hitchcock, David (2020). "Critical Thinking". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 1 November 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/critical-thinking/
Dewey, John (1910). "6: The Analysis of a Complete Act of Thought". How We Think. https://brocku.ca/MeadProject/Dewey/Dewey_1910a/Dewey_1910_f.html
Hitchcock, David (2020). "Critical Thinking". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 1 November 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/critical-thinking/
Hitchcock, David (2020). "Critical Thinking". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 1 November 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/critical-thinking/
Davies, Martin; Barnett, Ronald (2015). "Introduction". The Palgrave Handbook of Critical Thinking in Higher Education. Palgrave Macmillan US. pp. 1–25. doi:10.1057/9781137378057_1. ISBN 978-1-137-37805-7. 978-1-137-37805-7
Siegel, Harvey (2006). "Philosophy if Education, Epistemological Issues In". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. https://www.encyclopedia.com/humanities/encyclopedias-almanacs-transcripts-and-maps/philosophy-education-epistemological-issues
Siegel, Harvey (2006). "Philosophy if Education, Epistemological Issues In". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition. Macmillan. https://www.encyclopedia.com/humanities/encyclopedias-almanacs-transcripts-and-maps/philosophy-education-epistemological-issues
Davies, Martin; Barnett, Ronald (2015). "Introduction". The Palgrave Handbook of Critical Thinking in Higher Education. Palgrave Macmillan US. pp. 1–25. doi:10.1057/9781137378057_1. ISBN 978-1-137-37805-7. 978-1-137-37805-7
Hitchcock, David (2020). "Critical Thinking". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 1 November 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/critical-thinking/
Monteiro, Sandra; Sherbino, Jonathan; Sibbald, Matthew; Norman, Geoff (2020). "Critical thinking, biases and dual processing: The enduring myth of generalisable skills". Medical Education. 54 (1): 66–73. doi:10.1111/medu.13872. ISSN 1365-2923. PMID 31468581. S2CID 201674464. https://doi.org/10.1111%2Fmedu.13872
Hitchcock, David (2020). "Critical Thinking". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 1 November 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/critical-thinking/
Khalid, Ruhi (June 2010). "Positive Thinking in Coping with Stress and Health outcomes: Literature Review". Journal of Research and Reflections in Education. 4 (1): 42–61. https://www.academia.edu/30299598
Khalid, Ruhi (June 2010). "Positive Thinking in Coping with Stress and Health outcomes: Literature Review". Journal of Research and Reflections in Education. 4 (1): 42–61. https://www.academia.edu/30299598
Khalid, Ruhi (June 2010). "Positive Thinking in Coping with Stress and Health outcomes: Literature Review". Journal of Research and Reflections in Education. 4 (1): 42–61. https://www.academia.edu/30299598
Scheier, Michael F.; Carver, Charles S. (1 February 1993). "On the Power of Positive Thinking: The Benefits of Being Optimistic". Current Directions in Psychological Science. 2 (1): 26–30. doi:10.1111/1467-8721.ep10770572. ISSN 0963-7214. S2CID 145393172. https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/abs/10.1111/1467-8721.ep10770572?journalCode=cdpa
Khalid, Ruhi (June 2010). "Positive Thinking in Coping with Stress and Health outcomes: Literature Review". Journal of Research and Reflections in Education. 4 (1): 42–61. https://www.academia.edu/30299598
Khalid, Ruhi (June 2010). "Positive Thinking in Coping with Stress and Health outcomes: Literature Review". Journal of Research and Reflections in Education. 4 (1): 42–61. https://www.academia.edu/30299598
Scheier, Michael F.; Carver, Charles S. (1 February 1993). "On the Power of Positive Thinking: The Benefits of Being Optimistic". Current Directions in Psychological Science. 2 (1): 26–30. doi:10.1111/1467-8721.ep10770572. ISSN 0963-7214. S2CID 145393172. https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/abs/10.1111/1467-8721.ep10770572?journalCode=cdpa
Khalid, Ruhi (June 2010). "Positive Thinking in Coping with Stress and Health outcomes: Literature Review". Journal of Research and Reflections in Education. 4 (1): 42–61. https://www.academia.edu/30299598
Khalid, Ruhi (June 2010). "Positive Thinking in Coping with Stress and Health outcomes: Literature Review". Journal of Research and Reflections in Education. 4 (1): 42–61. https://www.academia.edu/30299598
Scheier, Michael F.; Carver, Charles S. (1 February 1993). "On the Power of Positive Thinking: The Benefits of Being Optimistic". Current Directions in Psychological Science. 2 (1): 26–30. doi:10.1111/1467-8721.ep10770572. ISSN 0963-7214. S2CID 145393172. https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/abs/10.1111/1467-8721.ep10770572?journalCode=cdpa
Khalid, Ruhi (June 2010). "Positive Thinking in Coping with Stress and Health outcomes: Literature Review". Journal of Research and Reflections in Education. 4 (1): 42–61. https://www.academia.edu/30299598
Khalid, Ruhi (June 2010). "Positive Thinking in Coping with Stress and Health outcomes: Literature Review". Journal of Research and Reflections in Education. 4 (1): 42–61. https://www.academia.edu/30299598
Khalid, Ruhi (June 2010). "Positive Thinking in Coping with Stress and Health outcomes: Literature Review". Journal of Research and Reflections in Education. 4 (1): 42–61. https://www.academia.edu/30299598
Scheier, Michael F.; Carver, Charles S. (1 February 1993). "On the Power of Positive Thinking: The Benefits of Being Optimistic". Current Directions in Psychological Science. 2 (1): 26–30. doi:10.1111/1467-8721.ep10770572. ISSN 0963-7214. S2CID 145393172. https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/abs/10.1111/1467-8721.ep10770572?journalCode=cdpa
Scheier, Michael F.; Carver, Charles S. (1 February 1993). "On the Power of Positive Thinking: The Benefits of Being Optimistic". Current Directions in Psychological Science. 2 (1): 26–30. doi:10.1111/1467-8721.ep10770572. ISSN 0963-7214. S2CID 145393172. https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/abs/10.1111/1467-8721.ep10770572?journalCode=cdpa
Oettingen, Gabriele; Cachia, Julie Y. A. (2017). "30. Problems with Positive Thinking and How to Overcome Them". Handbook of Self-Regulation: Third Edition: Research, Theory, and Applications. https://www.guilford.com/books/Handbook-of-Self-Regulation/Vohs-Baumeister/9781462533824/contents
Scheier, Michael F.; Carver, Charles S. (1 February 1993). "On the Power of Positive Thinking: The Benefits of Being Optimistic". Current Directions in Psychological Science. 2 (1): 26–30. doi:10.1111/1467-8721.ep10770572. ISSN 0963-7214. S2CID 145393172. https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/abs/10.1111/1467-8721.ep10770572?journalCode=cdpa
Thomas, Sandra P. (2020). "Defensive Pessimism". Encyclopedia of Personality and Individual Differences. Springer International Publishing. pp. 1036–1038. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-24612-3_1061. ISBN 978-3-319-24612-3. S2CID 243736790. 978-3-319-24612-3
Peale, Norman Vincent. The Power of Positive Thinking. Om Books International. ISBN 978-93-85609-89-3. 978-93-85609-89-3
Seligman, Martin E. P. (2002). "6. Optimism about the Future". Authentic Happiness: Using the New Positive Psychology to Realize Your Potential for Lasting Fulfillment. Simon and Schuster. ISBN 978-0-7432-4788-7. 978-0-7432-4788-7
Seligman, Martin E. P. (2002). "6. Optimism about the Future". Authentic Happiness: Using the New Positive Psychology to Realize Your Potential for Lasting Fulfillment. Simon and Schuster. ISBN 978-0-7432-4788-7. 978-0-7432-4788-7
Woodstock, Louise (1 April 2007). "Think About It: The Misbegotten Promise of Positive Thinking Discourse". Journal of Communication Inquiry. 31 (2): 166–189. doi:10.1177/0196859906298177. ISSN 0196-8599. S2CID 145436993. https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/abs/10.1177/0196859906298177
Chabris, Christopher F.; Simons, Daniel J. (24 September 2010). "Fight 'The Power'". The New York Times. https://www.nytimes.com/2010/09/26/books/review/Chabris-t.html