The signature of Peano arithmetic includes the addition, multiplication, and successor function symbols, the equality and less-than relation symbols, and a constant symbol for 0. The (well-formed) formulas of the language of first-order arithmetic are built up from these symbols together with the logical symbols in the usual manner of first-order logic.
The structure N {\displaystyle {\mathcal {N}}} is defined to be a model of Peano arithmetic as follows.
This structure is known as the standard model or intended interpretation of first-order arithmetic.
A sentence in the language of first-order arithmetic is said to be true in N {\displaystyle {\mathcal {N}}} if it is true in the structure just defined. The notation N ⊨ φ {\displaystyle {\mathcal {N}}\models \varphi } is used to indicate that the sentence φ {\displaystyle \varphi } is true in N . {\displaystyle {\mathcal {N}}.}
True arithmetic is defined to be the set of all sentences in the language of first-order arithmetic that are true in N {\displaystyle {\mathcal {N}}} , written Th( N {\displaystyle {\mathcal {N}}} ). This set is, equivalently, the (complete) theory of the structure N {\displaystyle {\mathcal {N}}} .2
The central result on true arithmetic is the undefinability theorem of Alfred Tarski (1936). It states that the set Th( N {\displaystyle {\mathcal {N}}} ) is not arithmetically definable. This means that there is no formula φ ( x ) {\displaystyle \varphi (x)} in the language of first-order arithmetic such that, for every sentence θ in this language,
Here # ( θ ) _ {\displaystyle {\underline {\#(\theta )}}} is the numeral of the canonical Gödel number of the sentence θ.
Post's theorem is a sharper version of the undefinability theorem that shows a relationship between the definability of Th( N {\displaystyle {\mathcal {N}}} ) and the Turing degrees, using the arithmetical hierarchy. For each natural number n, let Thn( N {\displaystyle {\mathcal {N}}} ) be the subset of Th( N {\displaystyle {\mathcal {N}}} ) consisting of only sentences that are Σ n 0 {\displaystyle \Sigma _{n}^{0}} or lower in the arithmetical hierarchy. Post's theorem shows that, for each n, Thn( N {\displaystyle {\mathcal {N}}} ) is arithmetically definable, but only by a formula of complexity higher than Σ n 0 {\displaystyle \Sigma _{n}^{0}} . Thus no single formula can define Th( N {\displaystyle {\mathcal {N}}} ), because
but no single formula can define Thn( N {\displaystyle {\mathcal {N}}} ) for arbitrarily large n.
As discussed above, Th( N {\displaystyle {\mathcal {N}}} ) is not arithmetically definable, by Tarski's theorem. A corollary of Post's theorem establishes that the Turing degree of Th( N {\displaystyle {\mathcal {N}}} ) is 0(ω), and so Th( N {\displaystyle {\mathcal {N}}} ) is not decidable nor recursively enumerable.
Th( N {\displaystyle {\mathcal {N}}} ) is closely related to the theory Th( R {\displaystyle {\mathcal {R}}} ) of the recursively enumerable Turing degrees, in the signature of partial orders.3 In particular, there are computable functions S and T such that:
True arithmetic is an unstable theory, and so has 2 κ {\displaystyle 2^{\kappa }} models for each uncountable cardinal κ {\displaystyle \kappa } . As there are continuum many types over the empty set, true arithmetic also has 2 ℵ 0 {\displaystyle 2^{\aleph _{0}}} countable models. Since the theory is complete, all of its models are elementarily equivalent.
The true theory of second-order arithmetic consists of all the sentences in the language of second-order arithmetic that are satisfied by the standard model of second-order arithmetic, whose first-order part is the structure N {\displaystyle {\mathcal {N}}} and whose second-order part consists of every subset of N {\displaystyle \mathbb {N} } .
The true theory of first-order arithmetic, Th( N {\displaystyle {\mathcal {N}}} ), is a subset of the true theory of second-order arithmetic, and Th( N {\displaystyle {\mathcal {N}}} ) is definable in second-order arithmetic. However, the generalization of Post's theorem to the analytical hierarchy shows that the true theory of second-order arithmetic is not definable by any single formula in second-order arithmetic.
Simpson (1977) has shown that the true theory of second-order arithmetic is computably interpretable with the theory of the partial order of all Turing degrees, in the signature of partial orders, and vice versa.
Boolos, Burgess & Jeffrey 2002, p. 295 - Boolos, George; Burgess, John P.; Jeffrey, Richard C. (2002), Computability and logic (4th ed.), Cambridge University Press, ISBN 978-0-521-00758-0 ↩
see theories associated with a structure /wiki/Theory_(mathematical_logic)#Theories_associated_with_a_structure ↩
Shore 2011, p. 184 - Shore, Richard (2011), "The recursively enumerable degrees", in Griffor, E.R. (ed.), Handbook of Computability Theory, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, vol. 140, North-Holland (published 1999), pp. 169–197, ISBN 978-0-444-54701-9 ↩