Menu
Home Explore People Places Arts History Plants & Animals Science Life & Culture Technology
On this page
Universal generalization
Rule in predicate logic

In predicate logic, generalization (also universal generalization, universal introduction, GEN, UG) is a valid inference rule. It states that if ⊢ P ( x ) {\displaystyle \vdash \!P(x)} has been derived, then ⊢ ∀ x P ( x ) {\displaystyle \vdash \!\forall x\,P(x)} can be derived.

We don't have any images related to Universal generalization yet.
We don't have any YouTube videos related to Universal generalization yet.
We don't have any PDF documents related to Universal generalization yet.
We don't have any Books related to Universal generalization yet.
We don't have any archived web articles related to Universal generalization yet.

Generalization with hypotheses

The full generalization rule allows for hypotheses to the left of the turnstile, but with restrictions. Assume Γ {\displaystyle \Gamma } is a set of formulas, φ {\displaystyle \varphi } a formula, and Γ ⊢ φ ( y ) {\displaystyle \Gamma \vdash \varphi (y)} has been derived. The generalization rule states that Γ ⊢ ∀ x φ ( x ) {\displaystyle \Gamma \vdash \forall x\,\varphi (x)} can be derived if y {\displaystyle y} is not mentioned in Γ {\displaystyle \Gamma } and x {\displaystyle x} does not occur in φ {\displaystyle \varphi } .

These restrictions are necessary for soundness. Without the first restriction, one could conclude ∀ x P ( x ) {\displaystyle \forall xP(x)} from the hypothesis P ( y ) {\displaystyle P(y)} . Without the second restriction, one could make the following deduction:

  1. ∃ z ∃ w ( z ≠ w ) {\displaystyle \exists z\,\exists w\,(z\not =w)} (Hypothesis)
  2. ∃ w ( y ≠ w ) {\displaystyle \exists w\,(y\not =w)} (Existential instantiation)
  3. y ≠ x {\displaystyle y\not =x} (Existential instantiation)
  4. ∀ x ( x ≠ x ) {\displaystyle \forall x\,(x\not =x)} (Faulty universal generalization)

This purports to show that ∃ z ∃ w ( z ≠ w ) ⊢ ∀ x ( x ≠ x ) , {\displaystyle \exists z\,\exists w\,(z\not =w)\vdash \forall x\,(x\not =x),} which is an unsound deduction. Note that Γ ⊢ ∀ y φ ( y ) {\displaystyle \Gamma \vdash \forall y\,\varphi (y)} is permissible if y {\displaystyle y} is not mentioned in Γ {\displaystyle \Gamma } (the second restriction need not apply, as the semantic structure of φ ( y ) {\displaystyle \varphi (y)} is not being changed by the substitution of any variables).

Example of a proof

Prove: ∀ x ( P ( x ) → Q ( x ) ) → ( ∀ x P ( x ) → ∀ x Q ( x ) ) {\displaystyle \forall x\,(P(x)\rightarrow Q(x))\rightarrow (\forall x\,P(x)\rightarrow \forall x\,Q(x))} is derivable from ∀ x ( P ( x ) → Q ( x ) ) {\displaystyle \forall x\,(P(x)\rightarrow Q(x))} and ∀ x P ( x ) {\displaystyle \forall x\,P(x)} .

Proof:

StepFormulaJustification
1 ∀ x ( P ( x ) → Q ( x ) ) {\displaystyle \forall x\,(P(x)\rightarrow Q(x))} Hypothesis
2 ∀ x P ( x ) {\displaystyle \forall x\,P(x)} Hypothesis
3 ( ∀ x ( P ( x ) → Q ( x ) ) ) → ( P ( y ) → Q ( y ) ) {\displaystyle (\forall x\,(P(x)\rightarrow Q(x)))\rightarrow (P(y)\rightarrow Q(y))} From (1) by Universal instantiation
4 P ( y ) → Q ( y ) {\displaystyle P(y)\rightarrow Q(y)} From (1) and (3) by Modus ponens
5 ( ∀ x P ( x ) ) → P ( y ) {\displaystyle (\forall x\,P(x))\rightarrow P(y)} From (2) by Universal instantiation
6 P ( y )   {\displaystyle P(y)\ } From (2) and (5) by Modus ponens
7 Q ( y )   {\displaystyle Q(y)\ } From (6) and (4) by Modus ponens
8 ∀ x Q ( x ) {\displaystyle \forall x\,Q(x)} From (7) by Generalization
9 ∀ x ( P ( x ) → Q ( x ) ) , ∀ x P ( x ) ⊢ ∀ x Q ( x ) {\displaystyle \forall x\,(P(x)\rightarrow Q(x)),\forall x\,P(x)\vdash \forall x\,Q(x)} Summary of (1) through (8)
10 ∀ x ( P ( x ) → Q ( x ) ) ⊢ ∀ x P ( x ) → ∀ x Q ( x ) {\displaystyle \forall x\,(P(x)\rightarrow Q(x))\vdash \forall x\,P(x)\rightarrow \forall x\,Q(x)} From (9) by Deduction theorem
11 ⊢ ∀ x ( P ( x ) → Q ( x ) ) → ( ∀ x P ( x ) → ∀ x Q ( x ) ) {\displaystyle \vdash \forall x\,(P(x)\rightarrow Q(x))\rightarrow (\forall x\,P(x)\rightarrow \forall x\,Q(x))} From (10) by Deduction theorem

In this proof, universal generalization was used in step 8. The deduction theorem was applicable in steps 10 and 11 because the formulas being moved have no free variables.

See also

References

  1. Copi and Cohen

  2. Hurley

  3. Moore and Parker