In Boolean logic, each variable denotes a truth value which can be either true (1), or false (0).
In a classical propositional calculus, each proposition will be assigned a truth value of either true or false.78 Some systems of classical logic include dedicated symbols for false (0 or ⊥ {\displaystyle \bot } ), while others instead rely upon formulas such as p ∧ ¬p and ¬(p → p).
In both Boolean logic and Classical logic systems, true and false are opposite with respect to negation; the negation of false gives true, and the negation of true gives false.
The negation of false is equivalent to the truth not only in classical logic and Boolean logic, but also in most other logical systems, as explained below.
False ∧ True = False (False AND anything is False).
False ∨ True = True (OR is True if at least one operand is True).
False → True = True (A false premise makes the implication vacuously true).
In most logical systems, negation, material conditional and false are related as:
In fact, this is the definition of negation in some systems,11 such as intuitionistic logic, and can be proven in propositional calculi where negation is a fundamental connective. Because p → p is usually a theorem or axiom, a consequence is that the negation of false (¬ ⊥) is true.
A contradiction is the situation that arises when a statement that is assumed to be true is shown to entail false (i.e., φ ⊢ ⊥). Using the equivalence above, the fact that φ is a contradiction may be derived, for example, from ⊢ ¬φ. A statement that entails false itself is sometimes called a contradiction, and contradictions and false are sometimes not distinguished, especially due to the Latin term falsum being used in English to denote either, but false is one specific proposition.
Logical systems may or may not contain the principle of explosion (ex falso quodlibet in Latin), ⊥ ⊢ φ for all φ. By that principle, contradictions and false are equivalent, since each entails the other.
Main article: Consistency
A formal theory using the " ⊥ {\displaystyle \bot } " connective is defined to be consistent, if and only if the false is not among its theorems. In the absence of propositional constants, some substitutes (such as the ones described above) may be used instead to define consistency.
Jennifer Fisher, On the Philosophy of Logic, Thomson Wadsworth, 2007, ISBN 0-495-00888-5, p. 17. /wiki/ISBN_(identifier) ↩
Willard Van Orman Quine, Methods of Logic, 4th ed, Harvard University Press, 1982, ISBN 0-674-57176-2, p. 34. /wiki/Willard_Van_Orman_Quine ↩
"Truth-value | logic". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 2020-08-15. https://www.britannica.com/topic/truth-value ↩
George Edward Hughes and D.E. Londey, The Elements of Formal Logic, Methuen, 1965, p. 151. /wiki/George_Edward_Hughes ↩
Leon Horsten and Richard Pettigrew, Continuum Companion to Philosophical Logic, Continuum International Publishing Group, 2011, ISBN 1-4411-5423-X, p. 199. /wiki/ISBN_(identifier) ↩
Graham Priest, An Introduction to Non-Classical Logic: From If to Is, 2nd ed, Cambridge University Press, 2008, ISBN 0-521-85433-4, p. 105. /wiki/Graham_Priest ↩
Aristotle (Organon) ↩
Barnes’ Complete Works of Aristotle (Princeton, 1984, Vol. 1): De Int.: pp. 25–38; Metaphysics IV: pp. 1588–1595. ↩
Gottlob Frege (1879, Begriffsschrift) ↩
Alfred Tarski (1930s, Introduction to Logic, Chapter II (Symbolic Logic)) ↩
Dov M. Gabbay and Franz Guenthner (eds), Handbook of Philosophical Logic, Volume 6, 2nd ed, Springer, 2002, ISBN 1-4020-0583-0, p. 12. /wiki/ISBN_(identifier) ↩