The relation between the premises and the conclusion of a deductive argument is usually referred to as "logical consequence". According to Alfred Tarski, logical consequence has 3 essential features: it is necessary, formal, and knowable a priori. It is necessary in the sense that the premises of valid deductive arguments necessitate the conclusion: it is impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion to be false, independent of any other circumstances. Logical consequence is formal in the sense that it depends only on the form or the syntax of the premises and the conclusion. This means that the validity of a particular argument does not depend on the specific contents of this argument. If it is valid, then any argument with the same logical form is also valid, no matter how different it is on the level of its contents. Logical consequence is knowable a priori in the sense that no empirical knowledge of the world is necessary to determine whether a deduction is valid. So it is not necessary to engage in any form of empirical investigation. Some logicians define deduction in terms of possible worlds: A deductive inference is valid if and only if, there is no possible world in which its conclusion is false while its premises are true. This means that there are no counterexamples: the conclusion is true in all such cases, not just in most cases.
It has been argued against this and similar definitions that they fail to distinguish between valid and invalid deductive reasoning, i.e. they leave it open whether there are invalid deductive inferences and how to define them. Some authors define deductive reasoning in psychological terms in order to avoid this problem. According to Mark Vorobey, whether an argument is deductive depends on the psychological state of the person making the argument: "An argument is deductive if, and only if, the author of the argument believes that the truth of the premises necessitates (guarantees) the truth of the conclusion". A similar formulation holds that the speaker claims or intends that the premises offer deductive support for their conclusion. This is sometimes categorized as a speaker-determined definition of deduction since it depends also on the speaker whether the argument in question is deductive or not. For speakerless definitions, on the other hand, only the argument itself matters independent of the speaker. One advantage of this type of formulation is that it makes it possible to distinguish between good or valid and bad or invalid deductive arguments: the argument is good if the author's belief concerning the relation between the premises and the conclusion is true, otherwise it is bad. One consequence of this approach is that deductive arguments cannot be identified by the law of inference they use. For example, an argument of the form modus ponens may be non-deductive if the author's beliefs are sufficiently confused. That brings with it an important drawback of this definition: it is difficult to apply to concrete cases since the intentions of the author are usually not explicitly stated.
Deductive arguments differ from non-deductive arguments in that the truth of their premises ensures the truth of their conclusion. There are two important conceptions of what this exactly means. They are referred to as the syntactic and the semantic approach. According to the syntactic approach, whether an argument is deductively valid depends only on its form, syntax, or structure. Two arguments have the same form if they use the same logical vocabulary in the same arrangement, even if their contents differ. For example, the arguments "if it rains then the street will be wet; it rains; therefore, the street will be wet" and "if the meat is not cooled then it will spoil; the meat is not cooled; therefore, it will spoil" have the same logical form: they follow the modus ponens. Their form can be expressed more abstractly as "if A then B; A; therefore B" in order to make the common syntax explicit. There are various other valid logical forms or rules of inference, like modus tollens or the disjunction elimination. The syntactic approach then holds that an argument is deductively valid if and only if its conclusion can be deduced from its premises using a valid rule of inference. One difficulty for the syntactic approach is that it is usually necessary to express the argument in a formal language in order to assess whether it is valid. This often brings with it the difficulty of translating the natural language argument into a formal language, a process that comes with various problems of its own. Another difficulty is due to the fact that the syntactic approach depends on the distinction between formal and non-formal features. While there is a wide agreement concerning the paradigmatic cases, there are also various controversial cases where it is not clear how this distinction is to be drawn.
The semantic approach suggests an alternative definition of deductive validity. It is based on the idea that the sentences constituting the premises and conclusions have to be interpreted in order to determine whether the argument is valid. This means that one ascribes semantic values to the expressions used in the sentences, such as the reference to an object for singular terms or to a truth-value for atomic sentences. The semantic approach is also referred to as the model-theoretic approach since the branch of mathematics known as model theory is often used to interpret these sentences. Usually, many different interpretations are possible, such as whether a singular term refers to one object or to another. According to the semantic approach, an argument is deductively valid if and only if there is no possible interpretation where its premises are true and its conclusion is false. Some objections to the semantic approach are based on the claim that the semantics of a language cannot be expressed in the same language, i.e. that a richer metalanguage is necessary. This would imply that the semantic approach cannot provide a universal account of deduction for language as an all-encompassing medium.
In some cases, whether a rule of inference is valid depends on the logical system one is using. The dominant logical system is classical logic and the rules of inference listed here are all valid in classical logic. But so-called deviant logics provide a different account of which inferences are valid. For example, the rule of inference known as double negation elimination, i.e. that if a proposition is not not true then it is also true, is accepted in classical logic but rejected in intuitionistic logic.
Modus ponens (also known as "affirming the antecedent" or "the law of detachment") is the primary deductive rule of inference. It applies to arguments that have as first premise a conditional statement (
P
→
Q
{\displaystyle P\rightarrow Q}
) and as second premise the antecedent (
P
{\displaystyle P}
) of the conditional statement. It obtains the consequent (
Q
{\displaystyle Q}
) of the conditional statement as its conclusion. The argument form is listed below:
In this form of deductive reasoning, the consequent (
Q
{\displaystyle Q}
) obtains as the conclusion from the premises of a conditional statement (
P
→
Q
{\displaystyle P\rightarrow Q}
) and its antecedent (
P
{\displaystyle P}
). However, the antecedent (
P
{\displaystyle P}
) cannot be similarly obtained as the conclusion from the premises of the conditional statement (
P
→
Q
{\displaystyle P\rightarrow Q}
) and the consequent (
Q
{\displaystyle Q}
). Such an argument commits the logical fallacy of affirming the consequent.
Modus tollens (also known as "the law of contrapositive") is a deductive rule of inference. It validates an argument that has as premises a conditional statement (formula) and the negation of the consequent (
¬
Q
{\displaystyle \lnot Q}
) and as conclusion the negation of the antecedent (
¬
P
{\displaystyle \lnot P}
). In contrast to modus ponens, reasoning with modus tollens goes in the opposite direction to that of the conditional. The general expression for modus tollens is the following:
In there being a subformula in common between the two premises that does not occur in the consequence, this resembles syllogisms in term logic, although it differs in that this subformula is a proposition whereas in Aristotelian logic, this common element is a term and not a proposition.
Various formal fallacies have been described. They are invalid forms of deductive reasoning. An additional aspect of them is that they appear to be valid on some occasions or on the first impression. They may thereby seduce people into accepting and committing them. One type of formal fallacy is affirming the consequent, as in "if John is a bachelor, then he is male; John is male; therefore, John is a bachelor". This is similar to the valid rule of inference named modus ponens, but the second premise and the conclusion are switched around, which is why it is invalid. A similar formal fallacy is denying the antecedent, as in "if Othello is a bachelor, then he is male; Othello is not a bachelor; therefore, Othello is not male". This is similar to the valid rule of inference called modus tollens, the difference being that the second premise and the conclusion are switched around. Other formal fallacies include affirming a disjunct, denying a conjunct, and the fallacy of the undistributed middle. All of them have in common that the truth of their premises does not ensure the truth of their conclusion. But it may still happen by coincidence that both the premises and the conclusion of formal fallacies are true.
Rules of inferences are definitory rules: they determine whether an argument is deductively valid or not. But reasoners are usually not just interested in making any kind of valid argument. Instead, they often have a specific point or conclusion that they wish to prove or refute. So given a set of premises, they are faced with the problem of choosing the relevant rules of inference for their deduction to arrive at their intended conclusion. This issue belongs to the field of strategic rules: the question of which inferences need to be drawn to support one's conclusion. The distinction between definitory and strategic rules is not exclusive to logic: it is also found in various games. In chess, for example, the definitory rules state that bishops may only move diagonally while the strategic rules recommend that one should control the center and protect one's king if one intends to win. In this sense, definitory rules determine whether one plays chess or something else whereas strategic rules determine whether one is a good or a bad chess player. The same applies to deductive reasoning: to be an effective reasoner involves mastering both definitory and strategic rules.
The example's first premise is false – there are people who eat carrots who are not quarterbacks – but the conclusion would necessarily be true, if the premises were true. In other words, it is impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false. Therefore, the argument is “valid”, but not “sound”. False generalizations – such as "Everyone who eats carrots is a quarterback" – are often used to make unsound arguments. The fact that there are some people who eat carrots but are not quarterbacks proves the flaw of the argument.
The support ampliative arguments provide for their conclusion comes in degrees: some ampliative arguments are stronger than others. This is often explained in terms of probability: the premises make it more likely that the conclusion is true. Strong ampliative arguments make their conclusion very likely, but not absolutely certain. An example of ampliative reasoning is the inference from the premise "every raven in a random sample of 3200 ravens is black" to the conclusion "all ravens are black": the extensive random sample makes the conclusion very likely, but it does not exclude that there are rare exceptions. In this sense, ampliative reasoning is defeasible: it may become necessary to retract an earlier conclusion upon receiving new related information. Ampliative reasoning is very common in everyday discourse and the sciences.
An important drawback of deductive reasoning is that it does not lead to genuinely new information. This means that the conclusion only repeats information already found in the premises. Ampliative reasoning, on the other hand, goes beyond the premises by arriving at genuinely new information. One difficulty for this characterization is that it makes deductive reasoning appear useless: if deduction is uninformative, it is not clear why people would engage in it and study it. It has been suggested that this problem can be solved by distinguishing between surface and depth information. On this view, deductive reasoning is uninformative on the depth level, in contrast to ampliative reasoning. But it may still be valuable on the surface level by presenting the information in the premises in a new and sometimes surprising way.
A popular misconception of the relation between deduction and induction identifies their difference on the level of particular and general claims. On this view, deductive inferences start from general premises and draw particular conclusions, while inductive inferences start from particular premises and draw general conclusions. This idea is often motivated by seeing deduction and induction as two inverse processes that complement each other: deduction is top-down while induction is bottom-up. But this is a misconception that does not reflect how valid deduction is defined in the field of logic: a deduction is valid if it is impossible for its premises to be true while its conclusion is false, independent of whether the premises or the conclusion are particular or general. Because of this, some deductive inferences have a general conclusion and some also have particular premises.
Another bias is called the "negative conclusion bias", which happens when one of the premises has the form of a negative material conditional, as in "If the card does not have an A on the left, then it has a 3 on the right. The card does not have a 3 on the right. Therefore, the card has an A on the left". The increased tendency to misjudge the validity of this type of argument is not present for positive material conditionals, as in "If the card has an A on the left, then it has a 3 on the right. The card does not have a 3 on the right. Therefore, the card does not have an A on the left".
Various psychological theories of deductive reasoning have been proposed. These theories aim to explain how deductive reasoning works in relation to the underlying psychological processes responsible. They are often used to explain the empirical findings, such as why human reasoners are more susceptible to some types of fallacies than to others.
Both mental logic theories and mental model theories assume that there is one general-purpose reasoning mechanism that applies to all forms of deductive reasoning. But there are also alternative accounts that posit various different special-purpose reasoning mechanisms for different contents and contexts. In this sense, it has been claimed that humans possess a special mechanism for permissions and obligations, specifically for detecting cheating in social exchanges. This can be used to explain why humans are often more successful in drawing valid inferences if the contents involve human behavior in relation to social norms. Another example is the so-called dual-process theory. This theory posits that there are two distinct cognitive systems responsible for reasoning. Their interrelation can be used to explain commonly observed biases in deductive reasoning. System 1 is the older system in terms of evolution. It is based on associative learning and happens fast and automatically without demanding many cognitive resources. System 2, on the other hand, is of more recent evolutionary origin. It is slow and cognitively demanding, but also more flexible and under deliberate control. The dual-process theory posits that system 1 is the default system guiding most of our everyday reasoning in a pragmatic way. But for particularly difficult problems on the logical level, system 2 is employed. System 2 is mostly responsible for deductive reasoning.
Deductivism is a philosophical position that gives primacy to deductive reasoning or arguments over their non-deductive counterparts. It is often understood as the evaluative claim that only deductive inferences are good or correct inferences. This theory would have wide-reaching consequences for various fields since it implies that the rules of deduction are "the only acceptable standard of evidence". This way, the rationality or correctness of the different forms of inductive reasoning is denied. Some forms of deductivism express this in terms of degrees of reasonableness or probability. Inductive inferences are usually seen as providing a certain degree of support for their conclusion: they make it more likely that their conclusion is true. Deductivism states that such inferences are not rational: the premises either ensure their conclusion, as in deductive reasoning, or they do not provide any support at all.
The focus on rules of inferences instead of axiom schemes is an important feature of natural deduction. But there is no general agreement on how natural deduction is to be defined. Some theorists hold that all proof systems with this feature are forms of natural deduction. This would include various forms of sequent calculi or tableau calculi. But other theorists use the term in a more narrow sense, for example, to refer to the proof systems developed by Gentzen and Jaskowski. Because of its simplicity, natural deduction is often used for teaching logic to students.
One recurrent criticism of philosophical systems build using the geometrical method is that their initial axioms are not as self-evident or certain as their defenders proclaim. This problem lies beyond the deductive reasoning itself, which only ensures that the conclusion is true if the premises are true, but not that the premises themselves are true. For example, Spinoza's philosophical system has been criticized this way based on objections raised against the causal axiom, i.e. that "the knowledge of an effect depends on and involves knowledge of its cause". A different criticism targets not the premises but the reasoning itself, which may at times implicitly assume premises that are themselves not self-evident.
Johnson-Laird, Phil (30 December 2009). "Deductive reasoning". WIREs Cognitive Science. 1 (1): 8–17. doi:10.1002/wcs.20. ISSN 1939-5078. PMID 26272833. https://wires.onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1002/wcs.20
Houde, R. "Deduction". New Catholic Encyclopedia. Modern logicians sometimes oppose deduction to induction on the basis that the first concludes from the general to the particular, whereas the second concludes from the particular to the general; this characterization is inaccurate, however, since deduction need not conclude to the particular and its process is far from being the logical inverse of the inductive procedure. https://www.encyclopedia.com/philosophy-and-religion/philosophy/philosophy-terms-and-concepts/deduction
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Norris, Stephen E. (1975). "The Intelligibility of Practical Reasoning". American Philosophical Quarterly. 12 (1): 77–84. ISSN 0003-0481. JSTOR 20009561. /wiki/ISSN_(identifier)
Evans, Jonathan (18 April 2005). "Deductive reasoning". In Morrison, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82417-0. 978-0-521-82417-0
McKeon, Matthew. "Logical Consequence". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 20 November 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/logcon/
Tarski, Alfred (1983). "On The Concept of Logical Consequence". Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics: Papers from 1923 to 1938. Hackett. ISBN 978-0-915-14476-1. 978-0-915-14476-1
McKeon, Matthew. "Logical Consequence". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 20 November 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/logcon/
Tarski, Alfred (1983). "On The Concept of Logical Consequence". Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics: Papers from 1923 to 1938. Hackett. ISBN 978-0-915-14476-1. 978-0-915-14476-1
McKeon, Matthew. "Logical Consequence". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 20 November 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/logcon/
Tarski, Alfred (1983). "On The Concept of Logical Consequence". Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics: Papers from 1923 to 1938. Hackett. ISBN 978-0-915-14476-1. 978-0-915-14476-1
McKeon, Matthew. "Logical Consequence". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 20 November 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/logcon/
Tarski, Alfred (1983). "On The Concept of Logical Consequence". Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics: Papers from 1923 to 1938. Hackett. ISBN 978-0-915-14476-1. 978-0-915-14476-1
Johnson-Laird, Phil (30 December 2009). "Deductive reasoning". WIREs Cognitive Science. 1 (1): 8–17. doi:10.1002/wcs.20. ISSN 1939-5078. PMID 26272833. https://wires.onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1002/wcs.20
Vorobej, Mark (1992). "Defining Deduction". Informal Logic. 14 (2). doi:10.22329/il.v14i2.2533. https://philpapers.org/rec/VORDD
Wilbanks, Jan J. (2010). "Defining Deduction, Induction, and Validity". Argumentation. 24 (1): 107–124. doi:10.1007/s10503-009-9131-5. S2CID 144481717. https://philpapers.org/rec/WILDDI
Vorobej, Mark (1992). "Defining Deduction". Informal Logic. 14 (2). doi:10.22329/il.v14i2.2533. https://philpapers.org/rec/VORDD
Copi, Irving M.; Cohen, Carl; Rodych, Victor (3 September 2018). "1. Basic Logical Concepts". Introduction to Logic. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-351-38696-8. 978-1-351-38696-8
IEP Staff. "Deductive and Inductive Arguments". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 28 May 2010. Retrieved 6 January 2022. https://web.archive.org/web/20100528032124/https://iep.utm.edu/ded-ind/
Wilbanks, Jan J. (2010). "Defining Deduction, Induction, and Validity". Argumentation. 24 (1): 107–124. doi:10.1007/s10503-009-9131-5. S2CID 144481717. https://philpapers.org/rec/WILDDI
Vorobej, Mark (1992). "Defining Deduction". Informal Logic. 14 (2). doi:10.22329/il.v14i2.2533. https://philpapers.org/rec/VORDD
Vorobej, Mark (1992). "Defining Deduction". Informal Logic. 14 (2). doi:10.22329/il.v14i2.2533. https://philpapers.org/rec/VORDD
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Johnson-Laird, Phil (30 December 2009). "Deductive reasoning". WIREs Cognitive Science. 1 (1): 8–17. doi:10.1002/wcs.20. ISSN 1939-5078. PMID 26272833. https://wires.onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1002/wcs.20
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Johnson-Laird, Phil (30 December 2009). "Deductive reasoning". WIREs Cognitive Science. 1 (1): 8–17. doi:10.1002/wcs.20. ISSN 1939-5078. PMID 26272833. https://wires.onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1002/wcs.20
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
"Philosophy of logic". Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 21 November 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/philosophy-of-logic
McKeon, Matthew. "Logical Consequence". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 20 November 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/logcon/
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Johnson-Laird, Phil (30 December 2009). "Deductive reasoning". WIREs Cognitive Science. 1 (1): 8–17. doi:10.1002/wcs.20. ISSN 1939-5078. PMID 26272833. https://wires.onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1002/wcs.20
Johnson-Laird, Phil (30 December 2009). "Deductive reasoning". WIREs Cognitive Science. 1 (1): 8–17. doi:10.1002/wcs.20. ISSN 1939-5078. PMID 26272833. https://wires.onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1002/wcs.20
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Evans, Jonathan (18 April 2005). "Deductive reasoning". In Morrison, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82417-0. 978-0-521-82417-0
Johnson-Laird, Phil (30 December 2009). "Deductive reasoning". WIREs Cognitive Science. 1 (1): 8–17. doi:10.1002/wcs.20. ISSN 1939-5078. PMID 26272833. https://wires.onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1002/wcs.20
Jaakko, Hintikka; Sandu, Gabriel (2006). "What is Logic?". Philosophy of Logic. North Holland. pp. 13–39. https://philpapers.org/rec/JAAWIL
Stump, David J. "Fallacy, Logical". New Dictionary of the History of Ideas. https://www.encyclopedia.com/history/dictionaries-thesauruses-pictures-and-press-releases/fallacy-logical
Craig, Edward (1996). "Formal and informal logic". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. https://philpapers.org/rec/BEAREO
McKeon, Matthew. "Logical Consequence". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 20 November 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/logcon/
Jaakko, Hintikka; Sandu, Gabriel (2006). "What is Logic?". Philosophy of Logic. North Holland. pp. 13–39. https://philpapers.org/rec/JAAWIL
McKeon, Matthew. "Logical Consequence". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 20 November 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/logcon/
Evans, Jonathan (18 April 2005). "Deductive reasoning". In Morrison, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82417-0. 978-0-521-82417-0
Jaakko, Hintikka; Sandu, Gabriel (2006). "What is Logic?". Philosophy of Logic. North Holland. pp. 13–39. https://philpapers.org/rec/JAAWIL
McKeon, Matthew. "Logical Consequence". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 20 November 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/logcon/
Evans, Jonathan (18 April 2005). "Deductive reasoning". In Morrison, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82417-0. 978-0-521-82417-0
Evans, Jonathan (18 April 2005). "Deductive reasoning". In Morrison, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82417-0. 978-0-521-82417-0
Jaakko, Hintikka; Sandu, Gabriel (2006). "What is Logic?". Philosophy of Logic. North Holland. pp. 13–39. https://philpapers.org/rec/JAAWIL
McKeon, Matthew. "Logical Consequence". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 20 November 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/logcon/
Evans, Jonathan (18 April 2005). "Deductive reasoning". In Morrison, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82417-0. 978-0-521-82417-0
Jaakko, Hintikka; Sandu, Gabriel (2006). "What is Logic?". Philosophy of Logic. North Holland. pp. 13–39. https://philpapers.org/rec/JAAWIL
MacFarlane, John (2017). "Logical Constants". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 21 November 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logical-constants/#SynTer
"Philosophy of logic". Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 21 November 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/philosophy-of-logic
Jaakko, Hintikka; Sandu, Gabriel (2006). "What is Logic?". Philosophy of Logic. North Holland. pp. 13–39. https://philpapers.org/rec/JAAWIL
McKeon, Matthew. "Logical Consequence". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 20 November 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/logcon/
Evans, Jonathan (18 April 2005). "Deductive reasoning". In Morrison, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82417-0. 978-0-521-82417-0
Jaakko, Hintikka; Sandu, Gabriel (2006). "What is Logic?". Philosophy of Logic. North Holland. pp. 13–39. https://philpapers.org/rec/JAAWIL
McKeon, Matthew. "Logical Consequence". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 20 November 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/logcon/
Jaakko, Hintikka; Sandu, Gabriel (2006). "What is Logic?". Philosophy of Logic. North Holland. pp. 13–39. https://philpapers.org/rec/JAAWIL
McKeon, Matthew. "Logical Consequence". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 20 November 2021. https://iep.utm.edu/logcon/
Evans, Jonathan (18 April 2005). "Deductive reasoning". In Morrison, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82417-0. 978-0-521-82417-0
Jaakko, Hintikka; Sandu, Gabriel (2006). "What is Logic?". Philosophy of Logic. North Holland. pp. 13–39. https://philpapers.org/rec/JAAWIL
"Philosophy of logic". Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 21 November 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/philosophy-of-logic
Shieh, Sanford (2006). "LOGICAL KNOWLEDGE". In Borchert, Donald (ed.). Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Vol. 2nd Edition. Macmillan. https://www.encyclopedia.com/humanities/encyclopedias-almanacs-transcripts-and-maps/logical-knowledge
Dowden, Bradley. "Fallacies". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 12 March 2022. https://iep.utm.edu/fallacy/
Stump, David J. "Fallacy, Logical". New Dictionary of the History of Ideas. https://www.encyclopedia.com/history/dictionaries-thesauruses-pictures-and-press-releases/fallacy-logical
Moschovakis, Joan (2021). "Intuitionistic Logic: 1. Rejection of Tertium Non Datur". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 11 December 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-intuitionistic/#RejTerNonDat
Borchert, Donald (2006). "Logic, Non-Classical". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Vol. 2nd. Macmillan. https://philpapers.org/rec/BORMEO
Morreau, Michael (2009). "The Hypothetical Syllogism". Journal of Philosophical Logic. 38 (4): 447–464. doi:10.1007/s10992-008-9098-y. ISSN 0022-3611. JSTOR 40344073. S2CID 34804481. /wiki/Doi_(identifier)
Dowden, Bradley. "Fallacies". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 12 March 2022. https://iep.utm.edu/fallacy/
Stump, David J. "Fallacy, Logical". New Dictionary of the History of Ideas. https://www.encyclopedia.com/history/dictionaries-thesauruses-pictures-and-press-releases/fallacy-logical
Hansen, Hans (2020). "Fallacies". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 12 March 2022. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/fallacies/
"Expert thinking and novice thinking: Deduction". Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 12 March 2022. https://www.britannica.com/topic/thought/Expert-thinking-and-novice-thinking
"Thought". Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 14 October 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/thought
Stone, Mark A. (2012). "Denying the Antecedent: Its Effective Use in Argumentation". Informal Logic. 32 (3): 327–356. doi:10.22329/il.v32i3.3681. https://philpapers.org/rec/STODTA
Dowden, Bradley. "Fallacies". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 12 March 2022. https://iep.utm.edu/fallacy/
Stump, David J. "Fallacy, Logical". New Dictionary of the History of Ideas. https://www.encyclopedia.com/history/dictionaries-thesauruses-pictures-and-press-releases/fallacy-logical
Jaakko, Hintikka; Sandu, Gabriel (2006). "What is Logic?". Philosophy of Logic. North Holland. pp. 13–39. https://philpapers.org/rec/JAAWIL
"Logical systems". Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 4 December 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/logic/Logical-systems
Pedemonte, Bettina (25 June 2018). "Strategic vs Definitory Rules: Their Role in Abductive Argumentation and their Relationship with Deductive Proof". Eurasia Journal of Mathematics, Science and Technology Education. 14 (9): em1589. doi:10.29333/ejmste/92562. ISSN 1305-8215. S2CID 126245285. https://www.ejmste.com/article/strategic-vs-definitory-rules-their-role-in-abductive-argumentation-and-their-relationship-with-5539
Jaakko, Hintikka; Sandu, Gabriel (2006). "What is Logic?". Philosophy of Logic. North Holland. pp. 13–39. https://philpapers.org/rec/JAAWIL
"Logical systems". Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 4 December 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/logic/Logical-systems
Pedemonte, Bettina (25 June 2018). "Strategic vs Definitory Rules: Their Role in Abductive Argumentation and their Relationship with Deductive Proof". Eurasia Journal of Mathematics, Science and Technology Education. 14 (9): em1589. doi:10.29333/ejmste/92562. ISSN 1305-8215. S2CID 126245285. https://www.ejmste.com/article/strategic-vs-definitory-rules-their-role-in-abductive-argumentation-and-their-relationship-with-5539
Jaakko, Hintikka; Sandu, Gabriel (2006). "What is Logic?". Philosophy of Logic. North Holland. pp. 13–39. https://philpapers.org/rec/JAAWIL
"Logical systems". Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 4 December 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/logic/Logical-systems
Jaakko, Hintikka; Sandu, Gabriel (2006). "What is Logic?". Philosophy of Logic. North Holland. pp. 13–39. https://philpapers.org/rec/JAAWIL
Jaakko, Hintikka; Sandu, Gabriel (2006). "What is Logic?". Philosophy of Logic. North Holland. pp. 13–39. https://philpapers.org/rec/JAAWIL
Backmann, Marius (1 June 2019). "Varieties of Justification—How (Not) to Solve the Problem of Induction". Acta Analytica. 34 (2): 235–255. doi:10.1007/s12136-018-0371-6. ISSN 1874-6349. S2CID 125767384. https://doi.org/10.1007%2Fs12136-018-0371-6
"Deductive and Inductive Arguments". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 28 May 2010. Retrieved 4 December 2021. https://web.archive.org/web/20100528032124/https://iep.utm.edu/ded-ind/
Jaakko, Hintikka; Sandu, Gabriel (2006). "What is Logic?". Philosophy of Logic. North Holland. pp. 13–39. https://philpapers.org/rec/JAAWIL
Backmann, Marius (1 June 2019). "Varieties of Justification—How (Not) to Solve the Problem of Induction". Acta Analytica. 34 (2): 235–255. doi:10.1007/s12136-018-0371-6. ISSN 1874-6349. S2CID 125767384. https://doi.org/10.1007%2Fs12136-018-0371-6
"Deductive and Inductive Arguments". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 28 May 2010. Retrieved 4 December 2021. https://web.archive.org/web/20100528032124/https://iep.utm.edu/ded-ind/
IEP Staff. "Deductive and Inductive Arguments". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 28 May 2010. Retrieved 6 January 2022. https://web.archive.org/web/20100528032124/https://iep.utm.edu/ded-ind/
Douven, Igor (2021). "Abduction". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/abduction/
IEP Staff. "Deductive and Inductive Arguments". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 28 May 2010. Retrieved 6 January 2022. https://web.archive.org/web/20100528032124/https://iep.utm.edu/ded-ind/
Douven, Igor (2021). "Abduction". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/abduction/
Borchert, Donald (2006). "G. W. Liebnitz". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy (in Portuguese) (2nd ed.). Macmillan. https://philpapers.org/rec/BORMEO
Scott, John; Marshall, Gordon (2009). "Analytic induction". A Dictionary of Sociology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-199-53300-8. 978-0-199-53300-8
Houde, R.; Camacho, L. "Induction". New Catholic Encyclopedia. https://www.encyclopedia.com/science-and-technology/computers-and-electrical-engineering/electrical-engineering/induction
Douven, Igor (2021). "Abduction". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/abduction/
Koslowski, Barbara (2017). "Abductive reasoning and explanation". International Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Routledge. doi:10.4324/9781315725697-20 (inactive 27 December 2024). ISBN 978-1-315-72569-7.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: DOI inactive as of December 2024 (link) 978-1-315-72569-7
IEP Staff. "Deductive and Inductive Arguments". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 28 May 2010. Retrieved 6 January 2022. https://web.archive.org/web/20100528032124/https://iep.utm.edu/ded-ind/
Hawthorne, James (2021). "Inductive Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 6 January 2022. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-inductive/
Douven, Igor (2021). "Abduction". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/abduction/
Jaakko, Hintikka; Sandu, Gabriel (2006). "What is Logic?". Philosophy of Logic. North Holland. pp. 13–39. https://philpapers.org/rec/JAAWIL
Backmann, Marius (1 June 2019). "Varieties of Justification—How (Not) to Solve the Problem of Induction". Acta Analytica. 34 (2): 235–255. doi:10.1007/s12136-018-0371-6. ISSN 1874-6349. S2CID 125767384. https://doi.org/10.1007%2Fs12136-018-0371-6
"Deductive and Inductive Arguments". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 28 May 2010. Retrieved 4 December 2021. https://web.archive.org/web/20100528032124/https://iep.utm.edu/ded-ind/
Hawthorne, James (2021). "Inductive Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 6 January 2022. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-inductive/
"Philosophy of logic". Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 21 November 2021. https://www.britannica.com/topic/philosophy-of-logic
Douven, Igor (2021). "Abduction". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/abduction/
Jaakko, Hintikka; Sandu, Gabriel (2006). "What is Logic?". Philosophy of Logic. North Holland. pp. 13–39. https://philpapers.org/rec/JAAWIL
Bunge, Mario (1960). "The Place of Induction in Science". Philosophy of Science. 27 (3): 262–270. doi:10.1086/287745. ISSN 0031-8248. JSTOR 185969. S2CID 120566417. /wiki/Doi_(identifier)
Evans, Jonathan (18 April 2005). "Deductive reasoning". In Morrison, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82417-0. 978-0-521-82417-0
Jaakko, Hintikka; Sandu, Gabriel (2006). "What is Logic?". Philosophy of Logic. North Holland. pp. 13–39. https://philpapers.org/rec/JAAWIL
Backmann, Marius (1 June 2019). "Varieties of Justification—How (Not) to Solve the Problem of Induction". Acta Analytica. 34 (2): 235–255. doi:10.1007/s12136-018-0371-6. ISSN 1874-6349. S2CID 125767384. https://doi.org/10.1007%2Fs12136-018-0371-6
"Deductive and Inductive Arguments". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 28 May 2010. Retrieved 4 December 2021. https://web.archive.org/web/20100528032124/https://iep.utm.edu/ded-ind/
Jaakko, Hintikka; Sandu, Gabriel (2006). "What is Logic?". Philosophy of Logic. North Holland. pp. 13–39. https://philpapers.org/rec/JAAWIL
D'Agostino, Marcello; Floridi, Luciano (2009). "The Enduring Scandal of Deduction: Is Propositional Logic Really Uninformative?". Synthese. 167 (2): 271–315. doi:10.1007/s11229-008-9409-4. hdl:2299/2995. ISSN 0039-7857. JSTOR 40271192. S2CID 9602882. /wiki/Doi_(identifier)
Jaakko, Hintikka; Sandu, Gabriel (2006). "What is Logic?". Philosophy of Logic. North Holland. pp. 13–39. https://philpapers.org/rec/JAAWIL
Evans, Jonathan (18 April 2005). "Deductive reasoning". In Morrison, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82417-0. 978-0-521-82417-0
Houde, R. "Deduction". New Catholic Encyclopedia. Modern logicians sometimes oppose deduction to induction on the basis that the first concludes from the general to the particular, whereas the second concludes from the particular to the general; this characterization is inaccurate, however, since deduction need not conclude to the particular and its process is far from being the logical inverse of the inductive procedure. https://www.encyclopedia.com/philosophy-and-religion/philosophy/philosophy-terms-and-concepts/deduction
Wilbanks, Jan J. (2010). "Defining Deduction, Induction, and Validity". Argumentation. 24 (1): 107–124. doi:10.1007/s10503-009-9131-5. S2CID 144481717. https://philpapers.org/rec/WILDDI
"Deductive and Inductive Arguments". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 17 March 2022. https://iep.utm.edu/deductive-inductive-arguments/
Houde, R. "Deduction". New Catholic Encyclopedia. Modern logicians sometimes oppose deduction to induction on the basis that the first concludes from the general to the particular, whereas the second concludes from the particular to the general; this characterization is inaccurate, however, since deduction need not conclude to the particular and its process is far from being the logical inverse of the inductive procedure. https://www.encyclopedia.com/philosophy-and-religion/philosophy/philosophy-terms-and-concepts/deduction
Wilbanks, Jan J. (2010). "Defining Deduction, Induction, and Validity". Argumentation. 24 (1): 107–124. doi:10.1007/s10503-009-9131-5. S2CID 144481717. https://philpapers.org/rec/WILDDI
Johnson-Laird, Phil (30 December 2009). "Deductive reasoning". WIREs Cognitive Science. 1 (1): 8–17. doi:10.1002/wcs.20. ISSN 1939-5078. PMID 26272833. https://wires.onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1002/wcs.20
Evans, Jonathan (18 April 2005). "Deductive reasoning". In Morrison, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82417-0. 978-0-521-82417-0
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Houde, R. "Deduction". New Catholic Encyclopedia. Modern logicians sometimes oppose deduction to induction on the basis that the first concludes from the general to the particular, whereas the second concludes from the particular to the general; this characterization is inaccurate, however, since deduction need not conclude to the particular and its process is far from being the logical inverse of the inductive procedure. https://www.encyclopedia.com/philosophy-and-religion/philosophy/philosophy-terms-and-concepts/deduction
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Evans, Jonathan (18 April 2005). "Deductive reasoning". In Morrison, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82417-0. 978-0-521-82417-0
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Evans, Jonathan (18 April 2005). "Deductive reasoning". In Morrison, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82417-0. 978-0-521-82417-0
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Evans, Jonathan (18 April 2005). "Deductive reasoning". In Morrison, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82417-0. 978-0-521-82417-0
Rips, Lance J. (1983). "Cognitive processes in propositional reasoning". Psychological Review. 90 (1): 38–71. doi:10.1037/0033-295X.90.1.38. ISSN 1939-1471. Retrieved 19 March 2022. https://doi.org/10.1037/0033-295X.90.1.38
Müller, Ulrich; Overton, Willis F.; Reene, Kelly (February 2001). "Development of Conditional Reasoning: A Longitudinal Study". Journal of Cognition and Development. 2 (1): 27–49. doi:10.1207/S15327647JCD0201_2. S2CID 143955563. /wiki/Doi_(identifier)
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Evans, Jonathan (18 April 2005). "Deductive reasoning". In Morrison, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82417-0. 978-0-521-82417-0
Evans, Jonathan (18 April 2005). "Deductive reasoning". In Morrison, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82417-0. 978-0-521-82417-0
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Evans, J. St B. T.; Lynch, J. S. (August 1973). "Matching Bias in the Selection Task". British Journal of Psychology. 64 (3): 391–397. doi:10.1111/j.2044-8295.1973.tb01365.x. /wiki/Doi_(identifier)
Wagner-Egger, Pascal (1 October 2007). "Conditional reasoning and the Wason selection task: Biconditional interpretation instead of reasoning bias". Thinking & Reasoning. 13 (4): 484–505. doi:10.1080/13546780701415979. ISSN 1354-6783. S2CID 145011175. https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/abs/10.1080/13546780701415979
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Evans, Jonathan (18 April 2005). "Deductive reasoning". In Morrison, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82417-0. 978-0-521-82417-0
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Evans, Jonathan (18 April 2005). "Deductive reasoning". In Morrison, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82417-0. 978-0-521-82417-0
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Evans, Jonathan (18 April 2005). "Deductive reasoning". In Morrison, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82417-0. 978-0-521-82417-0
Evans, Jonathan (18 April 2005). "Deductive reasoning". In Morrison, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82417-0. 978-0-521-82417-0
Chater, Nick; Oaksford, Mike; Hahn, Ulrike; Heit, Evan (2011). "Inductive Logic and Empirical Psychology". Inductive Logic. Handbook of the History of Logic. Vol. 10. North-Holland. pp. 553–624. doi:10.1016/B978-0-444-52936-7.50014-8. ISBN 978-0-444-52936-7. 978-0-444-52936-7
Arreckx, Frederique (2007). "Experiment 1: Affirmative and negative counterfactual questions". COUNTERFACTUAL THINKING AND THE FALSE BELIEF TASK: A DEVELOPMENTAL STUDY (Thesis). University of Plymouth. doi:10.24382/4506. hdl:10026.1/1758. http://hdl.handle.net/10026.1/1758
Evans, Jonathan (18 April 2005). "Deductive reasoning". In Morrison, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82417-0. 978-0-521-82417-0
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Johnson-Laird, Phil (30 December 2009). "Deductive reasoning". WIREs Cognitive Science. 1 (1): 8–17. doi:10.1002/wcs.20. ISSN 1939-5078. PMID 26272833. https://wires.onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1002/wcs.20
Johnson-Laird, Philip N.; Byrne, Ruth M. J. (1993). "Precis of Deduction". Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 16 (2): 323–333. doi:10.1017/s0140525x00030260. https://philpapers.org/rec/JOHPOD-2
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Johnson-Laird, Phil (30 December 2009). "Deductive reasoning". WIREs Cognitive Science. 1 (1): 8–17. doi:10.1002/wcs.20. ISSN 1939-5078. PMID 26272833. https://wires.onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1002/wcs.20
García-Madruga, Juan A.; Gutiérrez, Francisco; Carriedo, Nuria; Moreno, Sergio; Johnson-Laird, Philip N. (November 2002). "Mental Models in Deductive Reasoning". The Spanish Journal of Psychology. 5 (2): 125–140. doi:10.1017/s1138741600005904. PMID 12428479. S2CID 15293848. http://revistas.ucm.es/index.php/SJOP/article/view/SJOP0202220125A
Johnson-Laird, Philip N.; Byrne, Ruth M. J. (1993). "Precis of Deduction". Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 16 (2): 323–333. doi:10.1017/s0140525x00030260. https://philpapers.org/rec/JOHPOD-2
Johnson-Laird, Philip N.; Byrne, Ruth M. J. (1993). "Precis of Deduction". Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 16 (2): 323–333. doi:10.1017/s0140525x00030260. https://philpapers.org/rec/JOHPOD-2
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Johnson-Laird, Phil (30 December 2009). "Deductive reasoning". WIREs Cognitive Science. 1 (1): 8–17. doi:10.1002/wcs.20. ISSN 1939-5078. PMID 26272833. https://wires.onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1002/wcs.20
Johnson-Laird, Philip N.; Byrne, Ruth M. J. (1993). "Precis of Deduction". Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 16 (2): 323–333. doi:10.1017/s0140525x00030260. https://philpapers.org/rec/JOHPOD-2
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Johnson-Laird, Phil (30 December 2009). "Deductive reasoning". WIREs Cognitive Science. 1 (1): 8–17. doi:10.1002/wcs.20. ISSN 1939-5078. PMID 26272833. https://wires.onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1002/wcs.20
Johnson-Laird, Philip N.; Byrne, Ruth M. J. (1993). "Precis of Deduction". Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 16 (2): 323–333. doi:10.1017/s0140525x00030260. https://philpapers.org/rec/JOHPOD-2
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Johnson-Laird, Phil (30 December 2009). "Deductive reasoning". WIREs Cognitive Science. 1 (1): 8–17. doi:10.1002/wcs.20. ISSN 1939-5078. PMID 26272833. https://wires.onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1002/wcs.20
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
García-Madruga, Juan A.; Gutiérrez, Francisco; Carriedo, Nuria; Moreno, Sergio; Johnson-Laird, Philip N. (November 2002). "Mental Models in Deductive Reasoning". The Spanish Journal of Psychology. 5 (2): 125–140. doi:10.1017/s1138741600005904. PMID 12428479. S2CID 15293848. http://revistas.ucm.es/index.php/SJOP/article/view/SJOP0202220125A
Johnson-Laird, Philip N. (18 October 2010). "Mental models and human reasoning". Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences. 107 (43): 18243–18250. doi:10.1073/pnas.1012933107. ISSN 0027-8424. PMC 2972923. PMID 20956326. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC2972923
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Evans, Jonathan (18 April 2005). "Deductive reasoning". In Morrison, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82417-0. 978-0-521-82417-0
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Evans, Jonathan (18 April 2005). "Deductive reasoning". In Morrison, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82417-0. 978-0-521-82417-0
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Evans, Jonathan (18 April 2005). "Deductive reasoning". In Morrison, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82417-0. 978-0-521-82417-0
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Evans, Jonathan (18 April 2005). "Deductive reasoning". In Morrison, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82417-0. 978-0-521-82417-0
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Johnson-Laird, Phil (30 December 2009). "Deductive reasoning". WIREs Cognitive Science. 1 (1): 8–17. doi:10.1002/wcs.20. ISSN 1939-5078. PMID 26272833. https://wires.onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1002/wcs.20
Evans, Jonathan (18 April 2005). "Deductive reasoning". In Morrison, Robert (ed.). The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-82417-0. 978-0-521-82417-0
Johnson-Laird, Phil (30 December 2009). "Deductive reasoning". WIREs Cognitive Science. 1 (1): 8–17. doi:10.1002/wcs.20. ISSN 1939-5078. PMID 26272833. https://wires.onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1002/wcs.20
"Epistemology". Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 19 March 2022. https://www.britannica.com/topic/epistemology
Steup, Matthias; Neta, Ram (2020). "Epistemology". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 19 March 2022. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/epistemology/
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Becker, Kelly. "Reliabilism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 19 March 2022. https://iep.utm.edu/reliabil/
Goldman, Alvin; Beddor, Bob (2021). "Reliabilist Epistemology". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 19 March 2022. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/reliabilism/
Schechter, Joshua (2013). "Deductive Reasoning". The Encyclopedia of the Mind. SAGE Reference. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://philpapers.org/rec/SCHDR
Adams, Ernest W. (13 October 1998). "Deduction and Probability: What Probability Logic Is About". A Primer of Probability Logic. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-575-86066-4. 978-1-575-86066-4
Hájek, Alan (2001). "Probability, Logic, and Probability Logic". The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic. Blackwell. pp. 362–384. https://philpapers.org/rec/HJEPLA
Evans, Jonathan St. B. T.; Newstead, Stephen E.; Byrne, Ruth M. J., eds. (1993). Human Reasoning: The Psychology of Deduction (Repr. ed.). Psychology Press. p. 4. ISBN 978-0-863-77313-6. Retrieved 2015-01-26. In one sense [...] one can see the psychology of deductive reasoning as being as old as the study of logic, which originated in the writings of Aristotle. 978-0-863-77313-6
Samaha, Raid (3 March 2009). "Descartes' Project of Inquiry" (PDF). American University of Beirut. Archived from the original (PDF) on 28 September 2020. Retrieved 24 October 2019. https://web.archive.org/web/20200928144146/https://www.aub.edu.lb/fas/cvsp/Documents/Descartes.pdf
Bermejo-Luque, Lilian (2020). "What is Wrong with Deductivism?". Informal Logic. 40 (3): 295–316. doi:10.22329/il.v40i30.6214. S2CID 217418605. https://philpapers.org/rec/BERWIW-3
Howson, Colin (2000). "Deductivism". Hume's Problem. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0198250371.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-198-25037-1. 978-0-198-25037-1
Bermejo-Luque, Lilian (2020). "What is Wrong with Deductivism?". Informal Logic. 40 (3): 295–316. doi:10.22329/il.v40i30.6214. S2CID 217418605. https://philpapers.org/rec/BERWIW-3
Howson, Colin (2000). "Deductivism". Hume's Problem. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0198250371.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-198-25037-1. 978-0-198-25037-1
Kotarbinska, Janina (1977). "The Controversy: Deductivism Versus Inductivism". Twenty-Five Years of Logical Methodology in Poland. Springer Netherlands. pp. 261–278. doi:10.1007/978-94-010-1126-6_15. ISBN 978-9-401-01126-6. 978-9-401-01126-6
Stove, D. (1970). "Deductivism". Australasian Journal of Philosophy. 48 (1): 76–98. doi:10.1080/00048407012341481. https://philpapers.org/rec/STOD
Howson, Colin (2000). "Deductivism". Hume's Problem. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0198250371.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-198-25037-1. 978-0-198-25037-1
Henderson, Leah (2020). "The Problem of Induction". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 14 March 2022. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/induction-problem/
Stove, D. (1970). "Deductivism". Australasian Journal of Philosophy. 48 (1): 76–98. doi:10.1080/00048407012341481. https://philpapers.org/rec/STOD
Russell, Bertrand (2009) [1959]. "On Induction". The Problems of Philosophy – via Project Gutenberg. https://www.gutenberg.org/files/5827/5827-h/5827-h.htm
Thornton, Stephen (2021). "Karl Popper: 4. Basic Statements, Falsifiability and Convention". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 14 March 2022. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/popper/#BasiStatFalsConv
Shea, Brendan. "Popper, Karl: Philosophy of Science". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 14 March 2022. https://iep.utm.edu/pop-sci/
Howson, Colin (2000). "Deductivism". Hume's Problem. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/0198250371.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-198-25037-1. 978-0-198-25037-1
"hypothetico-deductive method". Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 14 March 2022. https://www.britannica.com/science/hypothetico-deductive-method
"hypothetico-deductive method". Oxford Reference. Retrieved 14 March 2022. https://www.oxfordreference.com/view/10.1093/oi/authority.20110803095954755
Indrzejczak, Andrzej. "Natural Deduction". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 15 March 2022. https://iep.utm.edu/natural-deduction/
Pelletier, Francis Jeffry; Hazen, Allen (2021). "Natural Deduction Systems in Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 15 March 2022. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/natural-deduction/
Gentzen, Gerhard (1934). "Untersuchungen über das logische Schließen. I". Mathematische Zeitschrift (in German). 39 (2): 176–210. doi:10.1007/BF01201353. S2CID 121546341. Ich wollte nun zunächst einmal einen Formalismus aufstellen, der dem wirklichen Schließen möglichst nahe kommt. So ergab sich ein "Kalkül des natürlichen Schließens. (First I wished to construct a formalism that comes as close as possible to actual reasoning. Thus arose a "calculus of natural deduction".) https://gdz.sub.uni-goettingen.de/id/PPN266833020_0039?tify={%22pages%22:%5b180%5d,%22panX%22:0.559,%22panY%22:0.785,%22view%22:%22info%22,%22zoom%22:0.411}
Indrzejczak, Andrzej. "Natural Deduction". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 15 March 2022. https://iep.utm.edu/natural-deduction/
Indrzejczak, Andrzej. "Natural Deduction". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 15 March 2022. https://iep.utm.edu/natural-deduction/
Pelletier, Francis Jeffry; Hazen, Allen (2021). "Natural Deduction Systems in Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 15 March 2022. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/natural-deduction/
Indrzejczak, Andrzej. "Natural Deduction". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 15 March 2022. https://iep.utm.edu/natural-deduction/
Pelletier, Francis Jeffry; Hazen, Allen (2021). "Natural Deduction Systems in Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 15 March 2022. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/natural-deduction/
Indrzejczak, Andrzej. "Natural Deduction". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 15 March 2022. https://iep.utm.edu/natural-deduction/
Pelletier, Francis Jeffry; Hazen, Allen (2021). "Natural Deduction Systems in Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 15 March 2022. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/natural-deduction/
In natural deduction, a simplified sequent consists of an environment
Γ
{\displaystyle \Gamma }
that yields (
⊢
{\displaystyle \vdash }
) a single conclusion
C
{\displaystyle C}
; a single sequent would take the form
"Assumptions A1, A2, A3 etc. yield Conclusion C1"; in the symbols of natural deduction,
Γ
A
1
,
A
2
,
A
3
.
.
.
⊢
C
1
{\displaystyle \Gamma A_{1},A_{2},A_{3}...\vdash C_{1}}
However if the premises were true but the conclusion were false, a hidden assumption could be intervening; alternatively, a hidden process might be coercing the form of presentation, and so forth; then the task would be to unearth the hidden factors in an ill-formed syllogism, in order to make the form valid.
see Deduction theorem
/wiki/Sequent
Indrzejczak, Andrzej. "Natural Deduction". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 15 March 2022. https://iep.utm.edu/natural-deduction/
Daly, Chris (2015). "Introduction and Historical Overview". The Palgrave Handbook of Philosophical Methods. Palgrave Macmillan. pp. 1–30. doi:10.1057/9781137344557_1. ISBN 978-1-137-34455-7. 978-1-137-34455-7
Dutton, Blake D. "Spinoza, Benedict De". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 16 March 2022. https://iep.utm.edu/spinoza/#H2
Goldenbaum, Ursula. "Geometrical Method". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 17 February 2022. https://iep.utm.edu/geo-meth/
Nadler, Steven (2006). "The geometric method". Spinoza's 'Ethics': An Introduction. Cambridge University Press. pp. 35–51. ISBN 978-0-521-83620-3. 978-0-521-83620-3
Daly, Chris (2015). "Introduction and Historical Overview". The Palgrave Handbook of Philosophical Methods. Palgrave Macmillan. pp. 1–30. doi:10.1057/9781137344557_1. ISBN 978-1-137-34455-7. 978-1-137-34455-7
Daly, Chris (2015). "Introduction and Historical Overview". The Palgrave Handbook of Philosophical Methods. Palgrave Macmillan. pp. 1–30. doi:10.1057/9781137344557_1. ISBN 978-1-137-34455-7. 978-1-137-34455-7
Doppelt, Torin (2010). "The Truth About 1A4". Spinoza's Causal Axiom: A Defense (PDF). https://qspace.library.queensu.ca/bitstream/handle/1974/6052/Doppelt_Torin_201009_MA.pdf
Daly, Chris (2015). "Introduction and Historical Overview". The Palgrave Handbook of Philosophical Methods. Palgrave Macmillan. pp. 1–30. doi:10.1057/9781137344557_1. ISBN 978-1-137-34455-7. 978-1-137-34455-7