A formal system is an abstract structure with specified properties used in deductive reasoning or alternatively an inductive system. The term formalism can also refer to specific styles of notation, such as Paul Dirac's bra–ket notation. In 1921, David Hilbert proposed using formal systems as the foundation of mathematics, but in 1931, Kurt Gödel demonstrated via Gödel's incompleteness theorem that any consistent formal system powerful enough to express arithmetic cannot prove its own completeness, indicating some statements remain unprovable and undermining Hilbert's original program.
Concepts
A formal system has the following:345
- Formal language, which is a set of well-formed formulas, which are strings of symbols from an alphabet, formed by a formal grammar (consisting of production rules or formation rules).
- Deductive system, deductive apparatus, or proof system, which has rules of inference that take axioms and infers theorems, both of which are part of the formal language.
A formal system is said to be recursive (i.e. effective) or recursively enumerable if the set of axioms and the set of inference rules are decidable sets or semidecidable sets, respectively.
Formal language
Main articles: Formal language, Formal grammar, Syntax (logic), and Logical form
A formal language is a language uses a set of strings whose symbols are taken from a specific alphabet, and operations used to form sentences from them. . Like languages in linguistics, formal languages generally have two aspects:
- the syntax is what the language looks like (more formally: the set of possible expressions that are valid utterances in the language)
- the semantics are what the utterances of the language mean (which is formalized in various ways, depending on the type of language in question)
Usually only the syntax of a formal language is considered via the notion of a formal grammar. The two main categories of formal grammar are that of generative grammars, which are sets of rules for how strings in a language can be written, and that of analytic grammars (or reductive grammar6[unreliable source?]7), which are sets of rules for how a string can be analyzed to determine whether it is a member of the language.
Deductive system
Main articles: Inference, Logical consequence, and Deductive reasoning
A deductive system, also called a deductive apparatus,8 consists of the axioms (or axiom schemata) and rules of inference that can be used to derive theorems of the system.9
In order to sustain its deductive integrity, a deductive apparatus must be definable without reference to any intended interpretation of the language. The aim is to ensure that each line of a derivation is merely a logical consequence of the lines that precede it. There should be no element of any interpretation of the language that gets involved with the deductive nature of the system.
The logical consequence (or entailment) of the system by its logical foundation is what distinguishes a formal system from others which may have some basis in an abstract model. Often the formal system will be the basis for or even identified with a larger theory or field (e.g. Euclidean geometry) consistent with the usage in modern mathematics such as model theory.
An example of a deductive system would be the rules of inference and axioms regarding equality used in first order logic.
The two main types of deductive systems are proof systems and formal semantics.1011
Proof system
Main articles: Proof system and Formal proof
Formal proofs are sequences of well-formed formulas (or WFF for short) that might either be an axiom or be the product of applying an inference rule on previous WFFs in the proof sequence. The last WFF in the sequence is recognized as a theorem.
Once a formal system is given, one can define the set of theorems which can be proved inside the formal system. This set consists of all WFFs for which there is a proof. Thus all axioms are considered theorems. Unlike the grammar for WFFs, there is no guarantee that there will be a decision procedure for deciding whether a given WFF is a theorem or not.
The point of view that generating formal proofs is all there is to mathematics is often called formalism. David Hilbert founded metamathematics as a discipline for discussing formal systems. Any language that one uses to talk about a formal system is called a metalanguage. The metalanguage may be a natural language, or it may be partially formalized itself, but it is generally less completely formalized than the formal language component of the formal system under examination, which is then called the object language, that is, the object of the discussion in question. The notion of theorem just defined should not be confused with theorems about the formal system, which, in order to avoid confusion, are usually called metatheorems.
Formal semantics of logical system
Main articles: Semantics of logic, Interpretation (logic), and Model theory
A logical system is a deductive system (most commonly first order logic) together with additional non-logical axioms. According to model theory, a logical system may be given interpretations which describe whether a given structure - the mapping of formulas to a particular meaning - satisfies a well-formed formula. A structure that satisfies all the axioms of the formal system is known as a model of the logical system.
A logical system is:
- Sound, if each well-formed formula that can be inferred from the axioms is satisfied by every model of the logical system.
- Semantically complete, if each well-formed formula that is satisfied by every model of the logical system can be inferred from the axioms.
An example of a logical system is Peano arithmetic. The standard model of arithmetic sets the domain of discourse to be the nonnegative integers and gives the symbols their usual meaning.12 There are also non-standard models of arithmetic.
History
Main articles: Formalism (philosophy of mathematics) and Formal logical systems
Early logic systems includes Indian logic of Pāṇini, syllogistic logic of Aristotle, propositional logic of Stoicism, and Chinese logic of Gongsun Long (c. 325–250 BCE). In more recent times, contributors include George Boole, Augustus De Morgan, and Gottlob Frege. Mathematical logic was developed in 19th century Europe.
David Hilbert instigated a formalist movement called Hilbert’s program as a proposed solution to the foundational crisis of mathematics, that was eventually tempered by Gödel's incompleteness theorems.13 The QED manifesto represented a subsequent, as yet unsuccessful, effort at formalization of known mathematics.
See also
- Systems science portal
- Philosophy portal
- List of formal systems
- Formal method – Mathematical program specificationsPages displaying short descriptions of redirect targets
- Formal science – Study of abstract structures described by formal systems
- Logic translation – Translation of a text into a logical system
- Rewriting system – Replacing subterm in a formula with another termPages displaying short descriptions of redirect targets
- Substitution instance – Concept in logicPages displaying short descriptions of redirect targets
- Theory (mathematical logic) – Set of sentences in a formal language
Sources
- Hunter, Geoffrey (1996) [1971]. Metalogic: An Introduction to the Metatheory of Standard First-Order Logic. University of California Press (published 1973). ISBN 9780520023567. OCLC 36312727. (accessible to patrons with print disabilities)
Further reading
- Hofstadter, Douglas, 1979. Gödel, Escher, Bach: An Eternal Golden Braid ISBN 978-0-465-02656-2. 777 pages.
- Kleene, Stephen C., 1967. Mathematical Logic Reprinted by Dover, 2002. ISBN 0-486-42533-9
- Smullyan, Raymond M., 1961. Theory of Formal Systems: Annals of Mathematics Studies, Princeton University Press (April 1, 1961) 156 pages ISBN 0-691-08047-X
External links
Look up formalisation in Wiktionary, the free dictionary.- Media related to Formal systems at Wikimedia Commons
- Encyclopædia Britannica, Formal system definition, 2007.
- Daniel Richardson, Formal systems, logic and semantics
- Formal System at PlanetMath.
- Encyclopedia of Mathematics, Formal system
- Peter Suber, Formal Systems and Machines: An Isomorphism Archived 2011-05-24 at the Wayback Machine, 1997.
- Ray Taol, Formal Systems
- What is a Formal System?: Some quotes from John Haugeland's `Artificial Intelligence: The Very Idea' (1985), pp. 48–64.
References
Hunter 1996, p. 7. - Hunter, Geoffrey (1996) [1971]. Metalogic: An Introduction to the Metatheory of Standard First-Order Logic. University of California Press (published 1973). ISBN 9780520023567. OCLC 36312727. https://search.worldcat.org/oclc/36312727 ↩
Zach, Richard (31 July 2003). "Hilbert's Program". Hilbert's Program, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/hilbert-program ↩
"Formal System". PlanetMath. https://planetmath.org/formalsystem ↩
Rapaport, William J. (25 March 2010). "Syntax & Semantics of Formal Systems". University of Buffalo. https://cse.buffalo.edu/~rapaport/formalsystems ↩
"Formal System". Pr ∞ {\displaystyle \infty } fWiki. https://proofwiki.org/Definition:Formal_System ↩
"Reductive grammar". Dictionary of Scientific and Technical Terms (6th ed.). McGraw-Hill. Reductive grammar: (computer science) A set of syntactic rules for the analysis of strings to determine whether the strings exist in a language. http://encyclopedia2.thefreedictionary.com/reductive+grammar ↩
Rulifson, Johns F. (April 1968). "A Tree Meta for the XDS 940" (PDF). Augmentation Research Center. Retrieved 30 November 2024. There are two classes of formal-language definition compiler-writing schemes. The productive grammar approach is the most common. A productive grammar consists primarrly of a set of rules that describe a method of generating all possible strings of the language. The reductive or analytical grammar technique states a set of rules that describe a method of analyzing any string of characters and deciding whether that string is in the language. /wiki/Jeff_Rulifson ↩
"Deductive Apparatus". Pr ∞ {\displaystyle \infty } fWiki. Retrieved 30 November 2024. https://proofwiki.org/Definition:Deductive_Apparatus ↩
Hunter 1996, p. 7. - Hunter, Geoffrey (1996) [1971]. Metalogic: An Introduction to the Metatheory of Standard First-Order Logic. University of California Press (published 1973). ISBN 9780520023567. OCLC 36312727. https://search.worldcat.org/oclc/36312727 ↩
"Deductive Apparatus". Pr ∞ {\displaystyle \infty } fWiki. Retrieved 30 November 2024. https://proofwiki.org/Definition:Deductive_Apparatus ↩
van Fraassen, Bas C. (2016) [1971]. Formal Semantics and Logic (PDF). Nousoul Digital Publishers. p. 12. Metalogic can in turn be roughly divided into two parts: proof theory and formal semantics... The division is not exact; many questions have been dealt with from both points of view, and some proof-theoretic methods and results are indispensable in semantics. /wiki/Bas_van_Fraassen ↩
Kaye, Richard (1991). "1. The Standard Model". Models of Peano arithmetic. Oxford: Clarendon Press. p. 10. ISBN 9780198532132. 9780198532132 ↩
Zach, Richard (31 July 2003). "Hilbert's Program". Hilbert's Program, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/hilbert-program ↩