Menu
Home Explore People Places Arts History Plants & Animals Science Life & Culture Technology
On this page
Reflexive relation
A binary relation over a set in which every element is related to itself
Transitive binary relations
  • v
  • t
  • e
Symmetric Antisymmetric Connected Well-founded Has joins Has meets Reflexive Irreflexive Asymmetric
Total, Semiconnex Anti-reflexive
Equivalence relation Y Y
Preorder (Quasiorder) Y
Partial order Y Y
Total preorder Y Y
Total order Y Y Y
Prewellordering Y Y Y
Well-quasi-ordering Y Y
Well-ordering Y Y Y Y
Lattice Y Y Y Y
Join-semilattice Y Y Y
Meet-semilattice Y Y Y
Strict partial order Y Y Y
Strict weak order Y Y Y
Strict total order Y Y Y Y
Symmetric Antisymmetric Connected Well-founded Has joins Has meets Reflexive Irreflexive Asymmetric
Definitions, for all a , b {\displaystyle a,b} and S ≠ ∅ : {\displaystyle S\neq \varnothing :} a R b ⇒ b R a {\displaystyle {\begin{aligned}&aRb\\\Rightarrow {}&bRa\end{aligned}}} a R b  and  b R a ⇒ a = b {\displaystyle {\begin{aligned}aRb{\text{ and }}&bRa\\\Rightarrow a={}&b\end{aligned}}} a ≠ b ⇒ a R b  or  b R a {\displaystyle {\begin{aligned}a\neq {}&b\Rightarrow \\aRb{\text{ or }}&bRa\end{aligned}}} min S exists {\displaystyle {\begin{aligned}\min S\\{\text{exists}}\end{aligned}}} a ∨ b exists {\displaystyle {\begin{aligned}a\vee b\\{\text{exists}}\end{aligned}}} a ∧ b exists {\displaystyle {\begin{aligned}a\wedge b\\{\text{exists}}\end{aligned}}} a R a {\displaystyle aRa} not  a R a {\displaystyle {\text{not }}aRa} a R b ⇒ not  b R a {\displaystyle {\begin{aligned}aRb\Rightarrow \\{\text{not }}bRa\end{aligned}}}
Y indicates that the column's property is always true for the row's term (at the very left), while ✗ indicates that the property is not guaranteed in general (it might, or might not, hold). For example, that every equivalence relation is symmetric, but not necessarily antisymmetric, is indicated by Y in the "Symmetric" column and ✗ in the "Antisymmetric" column, respectively.

All definitions tacitly require the homogeneous relation R {\displaystyle R} be transitive: for all a , b , c , {\displaystyle a,b,c,} if a R b {\displaystyle aRb} and b R c {\displaystyle bRc} then a R c . {\displaystyle aRc.} A term's definition may require additional properties that are not listed in this table.

In mathematics, a binary relation R {\displaystyle R} on a set X {\displaystyle X} is reflexive if it relates every element of X {\displaystyle X} to itself.

An example of a reflexive relation is the relation "is equal to" on the set of real numbers, since every real number is equal to itself. A reflexive relation is said to have the reflexive property or is said to possess reflexivity. Along with symmetry and transitivity, reflexivity is one of three properties defining equivalence relations.

We don't have any images related to Reflexive relation yet.
We don't have any YouTube videos related to Reflexive relation yet.
We don't have any PDF documents related to Reflexive relation yet.
We don't have any Books related to Reflexive relation yet.
We don't have any archived web articles related to Reflexive relation yet.

Etymology

The word reflexive is originally derived from the Medieval Latin reflexivus ('recoiling' [c.f. reflex], or 'directed upon itself') (c. 1250 AD) from the classical Latin reflexus- ('turn away', 'reflection') + -īvus (suffix). The word entered Early Modern English in the 1580s. The sense of the word meaning 'directed upon itself', as now used in mathematics, surviving mostly by its use in philosophy and grammar (c.f. Reflexive verb and Reflexive pronoun).34

The first explicit use of "reflexivity", that is, describing a relation as having the property that every element is related to itself, is generally attributed to Giuseppe Peano in his Arithmetices principia (1889), wherein he defines one of the fundamental properties of equality being a = a {\displaystyle a=a} .56 The first use of the word reflexive in the sense of mathematics and logic was by Bertrand Russell in his Principles of Mathematics (1903).78

Definitions

A relation R {\displaystyle R} on the set X {\displaystyle X} is said to be reflexive if for every x ∈ X {\displaystyle x\in X} , ( x , x ) ∈ R {\displaystyle (x,x)\in R} .

Equivalently, letting I X := { ( x , x )   :   x ∈ X } {\displaystyle \operatorname {I} _{X}:=\{(x,x)~:~x\in X\}} denote the identity relation on X {\displaystyle X} , the relation R {\displaystyle R} is reflexive if I X ⊆ R {\displaystyle \operatorname {I} _{X}\subseteq R} .

The reflexive closure of R {\displaystyle R} is the union R ∪ I X , {\displaystyle R\cup \operatorname {I} _{X},} which can equivalently be defined as the smallest (with respect to ⊆ {\displaystyle \subseteq } ) reflexive relation on X {\displaystyle X} that is a superset of R . {\displaystyle R.} A relation R {\displaystyle R} is reflexive if and only if it is equal to its reflexive closure.

The reflexive reduction or irreflexive kernel of R {\displaystyle R} is the smallest (with respect to ⊆ {\displaystyle \subseteq } ) relation on X {\displaystyle X} that has the same reflexive closure as R . {\displaystyle R.} It is equal to R ∖ I X = { ( x , y ) ∈ R   :   x ≠ y } . {\displaystyle R\setminus \operatorname {I} _{X}=\{(x,y)\in R~:~x\neq y\}.} The reflexive reduction of R {\displaystyle R} can, in a sense, be seen as a construction that is the "opposite" of the reflexive closure of R . {\displaystyle R.} For example, the reflexive closure of the canonical strict inequality < {\displaystyle <} on the reals R {\displaystyle \mathbb {R} } is the usual non-strict inequality ≤ {\displaystyle \leq } whereas the reflexive reduction of ≤ {\displaystyle \leq } is < . {\displaystyle <.}

Related definitions

There are several definitions related to the reflexive property. The relation R {\displaystyle R} is called:

irreflexive, anti-reflexive or aliorelative 9 if it does not relate any element to itself; that is, if x R x {\displaystyle xRx} holds for no x ∈ X . {\displaystyle x\in X.} A relation is irreflexive if and only if its complement in X × X {\displaystyle X\times X} is reflexive. An asymmetric relation is necessarily irreflexive. A transitive and irreflexive relation is necessarily asymmetric. left quasi-reflexive if whenever x , y ∈ X {\displaystyle x,y\in X} are such that x R y , {\displaystyle xRy,} then necessarily x R x . {\displaystyle xRx.} 10 right quasi-reflexive if whenever x , y ∈ X {\displaystyle x,y\in X} are such that x R y , {\displaystyle xRy,} then necessarily y R y . {\displaystyle yRy.} quasi-reflexive if every element that is part of some relation is related to itself. Explicitly, this means that whenever x , y ∈ X {\displaystyle x,y\in X} are such that x R y , {\displaystyle xRy,} then necessarily x R x {\displaystyle xRx} and y R y . {\displaystyle yRy.} Equivalently, a binary relation is quasi-reflexive if and only if it is both left quasi-reflexive and right quasi-reflexive. A relation R {\displaystyle R} is quasi-reflexive if and only if its symmetric closure R ∪ R T {\displaystyle R\cup R^{\operatorname {T} }} is left (or right) quasi-reflexive. antisymmetric if whenever x , y ∈ X {\displaystyle x,y\in X} are such that x R y  and  y R x , {\displaystyle xRy{\text{ and }}yRx,} then necessarily x = y . {\displaystyle x=y.} coreflexive if whenever x , y ∈ X {\displaystyle x,y\in X} are such that x R y , {\displaystyle xRy,} then necessarily x = y . {\displaystyle x=y.} 11 A relation R {\displaystyle R} is coreflexive if and only if its symmetric closure is anti-symmetric.

A reflexive relation on a nonempty set X {\displaystyle X} can neither be irreflexive, nor asymmetric ( R {\displaystyle R} is called asymmetric if x R y {\displaystyle xRy} implies not y R x {\displaystyle yRx} ), nor antitransitive ( R {\displaystyle R} is antitransitive if x R y  and  y R z {\displaystyle xRy{\text{ and }}yRz} implies not x R z {\displaystyle xRz} ).

Examples

Examples of reflexive relations include:

  • "is equal to" (equality)
  • "is a subset of" (set inclusion)
  • "divides" (divisibility)
  • "is greater than or equal to"
  • "is less than or equal to"

Examples of irreflexive relations include:

  • "is not equal to"
  • "is coprime to" on the integers larger than 1
  • "is a proper subset of"
  • "is greater than"
  • "is less than"

An example of an irreflexive relation, which means that it does not relate any element to itself, is the "greater than" relation ( x > y {\displaystyle x>y} ) on the real numbers. Not every relation which is not reflexive is irreflexive; it is possible to define relations where some elements are related to themselves but others are not (that is, neither all nor none are). For example, the binary relation "the product of x {\displaystyle x} and y {\displaystyle y} is even" is reflexive on the set of even numbers, irreflexive on the set of odd numbers, and neither reflexive nor irreflexive on the set of natural numbers.

An example of a quasi-reflexive relation R {\displaystyle R} is "has the same limit as" on the set of sequences of real numbers: not every sequence has a limit, and thus the relation is not reflexive, but if a sequence has the same limit as some sequence, then it has the same limit as itself. An example of a left quasi-reflexive relation is a left Euclidean relation, which is always left quasi-reflexive but not necessarily right quasi-reflexive, and thus not necessarily quasi-reflexive.

An example of a coreflexive relation is the relation on integers in which each odd number is related to itself and there are no other relations. The equality relation is the only example of a both reflexive and coreflexive relation, and any coreflexive relation is a subset of the identity relation. The union of a coreflexive relation and a transitive relation on the same set is always transitive.

Number of reflexive relations

The number of reflexive relations on an n {\displaystyle n} -element set is 2 n 2 − n . {\displaystyle 2^{n^{2}-n}.} 12

Number of n-element binary relations of different types
Elem­entsAnyTransitiveReflexiveSymmetricPreorderPartial orderTotal preorderTotal orderEquivalence relation
0111111111
1221211111
216134843322
3512171646429191365
465,5363,9944,0961,024355219752415
n2n22n(n−1)2n(n+1)/2nk=0 k!S(n, k)n!nk=0 S(n, k)
OEISA002416A006905A053763A006125A000798A001035A000670A000142A000110

Note that S(n, k) refers to Stirling numbers of the second kind.

Philosophical logic

Authors in philosophical logic often use different terminology. Reflexive relations in the mathematical sense are called totally reflexive in philosophical logic, and quasi-reflexive relations are called reflexive.1314

Notes

  • Clarke, D.S.; Behling, Richard (1998). Deductive Logic – An Introduction to Evaluation Techniques and Logical Theory. University Press of America. ISBN 0-7618-0922-8.
  • Fonseca de Oliveira, José Nuno; Pereira Cunha Rodrigues, César de Jesus (2004), "Transposing relations: from Maybe functions to hash tables", Mathematics of Program Construction, Lecture Notes in Computer Science, 3125, Springer: 334–356, doi:10.1007/978-3-540-27764-4_18, ISBN 978-3-540-22380-1
  • Hausman, Alan; Kahane, Howard; Tidman, Paul (2013). Logic and Philosophy – A Modern Introduction. Wadsworth. ISBN 978-1-133-05000-1.
  • Levy, A. (1979), Basic Set Theory, Perspectives in Mathematical Logic, Dover, ISBN 0-486-42079-5
  • Lidl, R.; Pilz, G. (1998), Applied abstract algebra, Undergraduate Texts in Mathematics, Springer-Verlag, ISBN 0-387-98290-6
  • Quine, W. V. (1951), Mathematical Logic, Revised Edition, Reprinted 2003, Harvard University Press, ISBN 0-674-55451-5 {{citation}}: ISBN / Date incompatibility (help)
  • Russell, Bertrand (1920). Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy (PDF) (2nd ed.). London: George Allen & Unwin, Ltd. (Online corrected edition, Feb 2010)
  • Schmidt, Gunther (2010), Relational Mathematics, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 978-0-521-76268-7

References

  1. Levy 1979, p. 74 - Levy, A. (1979), Basic Set Theory, Perspectives in Mathematical Logic, Dover, ISBN 0-486-42079-5

  2. Schmidt 2010 - Schmidt, Gunther (2010), Relational Mathematics, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 978-0-521-76268-7

  3. "reflexive | Etymology of reflexive by etymonline". www.etymonline.com. Retrieved 2024-12-22. https://www.etymonline.com/word/reflexive#etymonline_v_37000

  4. Oxford English Dictionary, s.v. “Reflexive (adj. & n.), Etymology,” September 2024. /wiki/Oxford_English_Dictionary

  5. Peano, Giuseppe (1889). Arithmetices principia: nova methodo (in Latin). Fratres Bocca. pp. XIII. Archived from the original on 2009-07-15. /wiki/Giuseppe_Peano

  6. Russell, Bertrand (1903). "Principles of Mathematics". Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780203864760. ISBN 978-1-135-22311-3. {{cite journal}}: ISBN / Date incompatibility (help) 978-1-135-22311-3

  7. Russell, Bertrand (1903). "Principles of Mathematics". Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780203864760. ISBN 978-1-135-22311-3. {{cite journal}}: ISBN / Date incompatibility (help) 978-1-135-22311-3

  8. Oxford English Dictionary, s.v. “Reflexive (adj.), sense 7 - Mathematics and Logic”, "1903–", September 2024. /wiki/Oxford_English_Dictionary

  9. This term is due to C S Peirce; see Russell 1920, p. 32. Russell also introduces two equivalent terms to be contained in or imply diversity. /wiki/C_S_Peirce

  10. The Encyclopædia Britannica calls this property quasi-reflexivity. https://www.britannica.com/topic/formal-logic/Logical-manipulations-in-LPC#ref534730

  11. Fonseca de Oliveira & Pereira Cunha Rodrigues 2004, p. 337 - Fonseca de Oliveira, José Nuno; Pereira Cunha Rodrigues, César de Jesus (2004), "Transposing relations: from Maybe functions to hash tables", Mathematics of Program Construction, Lecture Notes in Computer Science, 3125, Springer: 334–356, doi:10.1007/978-3-540-27764-4_18, ISBN 978-3-540-22380-1 https://doi.org/10.1007%2F978-3-540-27764-4_18

  12. On-Line Encyclopedia of Integer Sequences A053763 //oeis.org/A053763

  13. Hausman, Kahane & Tidman 2013, pp. 327–328 - Hausman, Alan; Kahane, Howard; Tidman, Paul (2013). Logic and Philosophy – A Modern Introduction. Wadsworth. ISBN 978-1-133-05000-1.

  14. Clarke & Behling 1998, p. 187 - Clarke, D.S.; Behling, Richard (1998). Deductive Logic – An Introduction to Evaluation Techniques and Logical Theory. University Press of America. ISBN 0-7618-0922-8.