The mind is the totality of psychological phenomena and capacities, encompassing both conscious and unconscious states. The term mind is sometimes used in a narrow meaning to refer only to cognitive functions associated with perception, reasoning, awareness, and memory. In a broader sense, it also includes processes like feeling, motivation, and behavior. The precise definition of mind is disputed and while it is generally accepted that some non-human animals also have minds, there is no agreement on where exactly the boundary lies. Despite these disputes, there is wide agreement that mind plays a central role in most aspects of human life as the seat of consciousness, emotions, thoughts, and sense of personal identity. Various fields of inquiry study the mind; the main ones include psychology, cognitive science, neuroscience, and philosophy of mind.
Imagination is a creative process of internally generating mental images, ideas, experiences, and related phenomena. Unlike perception, it does not directly depend on the stimulation of sensory organs. Similar to dreaming, these mental constructs are often derived from previous experiences but can include novel combinations and elements. Imagination happens during daydreaming and plays a key role in art and literature. Additionally, it can also be used to come up with novel solutions to real-world problems.
Motivation is an internal state that propels individuals to initiate, continue, or terminate goal-directed behavior. It is responsible for the formation of intentions to perform actions and affects what goals someone pursues, how much effort they invest in the activity, and how long they engage in it. Motivation is affected by emotions, which are temporary experiences of positive or negative feelings like joy or anger. They are directed at and evaluate specific events, persons, or situations. They usually come together with certain physiological and behavioral responses.
Attention is an aspect of other mental processes in which mental resources like awareness are directed towards certain features of experience and away from others. This happens when a driver focuses on traffic while ignoring billboards on the side of the road. Attention can be controlled voluntarily in the pursuit of specific goals but can also be diverted involuntarily when a strong stimulus captures a person's attention. Attention is relevant to learning, which is the ability of the mind to acquire new information and permanently modify its understanding and behavioral patterns. Individuals learn by undergoing experiences, which helps them adapt to the environment.
An influential distinction is between conscious and unconscious mental processes. Consciousness is the awareness of external and internal circumstances. It encompasses a wide variety of states, such as perception, thinking, fantasizing, dreaming, and altered states of consciousness. In the case of phenomenal consciousness, the awareness involves a direct and qualitative experience of mental phenomena, like the auditory experience of attending a concert. Access consciousness, by contrast, refers to an awareness of information that is accessible to other mental processes but not necessarily part of current experience. For example, the information stored in a memory may be accessible when drawing conclusions or guiding actions even when the person is not explicitly thinking about it.
Unconscious or nonconscious mental processes operate without the individual's awareness but can still influence mental phenomena on the level of thought, feeling, and action. Some theorists distinguish between preconscious, subconscious, and unconscious states depending on their accessibility to conscious awareness. When applied to the overall state of a person rather than specific processes, the term unconscious implies that the person lacks any awareness of their environment and themselves, like during a coma. The unconscious mind plays a central role in psychoanalysis as the part of the mind that contains thoughts, memories, and desires not accessible to conscious introspection. According to Sigmund Freud, the psychological mechanism of repression keeps disturbing phenomena, like unacceptable sexual and aggressive impulses, from entering consciousness to protect the individual. Psychoanalytic theory studies symptoms caused by this process and therapeutic methods to avoid them by making the repressed thoughts accessible to conscious awareness.
In contrast to the traditional view, more recent approaches analyze the mind in terms of mental modules rather than faculties. A mental module is an inborn system of the brain that automatically performs a particular function within a specific domain without conscious awareness or effort. In contrast to faculties, the concept of mental modules is normally used to provide a more limited explanation. It is typically restricted to certain low-level cognitive processes without trying to explain how they are integrated into higher-level processes such as conscious reasoning. Many low-level cognitive processes responsible for visual perception have this automatic and unconscious nature. In the case of visual illusions like the Müller-Lyer illusion, the underlying processes continue their operation and the illusion persists even after a person has become aware of the illusion, indicating the mechanical and involuntary nature of the process. Other examples of mental modules concern cognitive processes responsible for language processing and facial recognition.
A related view asserts that all mental states are either conscious or accessible to consciousness. According to this view, when a person actively remembers the fact that the Eiffel Tower is in Paris then this state is mental because it is part of consciousness. When the person does not think about it, this belief is still considered a mental state because the person could bring it to consciousness by thinking about it. This view denies the existence of a "deep unconsciousness", that is, unconscious mental states that cannot in principle become conscious.
The mind–body problem is the difficulty of providing a general explanation of the relationship between mind and body, for example, of the link between thoughts and brain processes. Despite their different characteristics, mind and body interact with each other, like when a bodily change causes mental discomfort or when a limb moves because of an intention. The mind–body problem came to particular prominence in modern philosophy as a result of Descartes' metaphysical distinction between mind and body. Earlier philosophers typically did not see mind and body as contrasting principles. Following Descartes' philosophy, minds were often conceived as substantial entities able to exist on their own. Now they are more commonly seen as capacities rather than independent entities.
Another approach to the relation between mind and matter uses empirical observation to study how the brain works and which brain areas and processes are associated with specific mental phenomena. The brain is the central organ of the nervous system and is present in all vertebrates and the majority of invertebrates. The human brain is of particular complexity and consists of about 86 billion neurons, which communicate with one another via synapses. They form a complex neural network and cognitive processes emerge from their electrical and chemical interactions. The human brain is divided into regions that are associated with different functions. The main regions are the hindbrain, midbrain, and forebrain. Many biological functions associated with basic survival are the responsibility of the hindbrain and midbrain. Higher mental functions, ranging from thoughts to motivation, are primarily localized in the forebrain.
The primary operations of many of the main mental phenomena are located in specific areas of the forebrain. The prefrontal cortex is responsible for executive functions, such as planning, decision-making, problem-solving, and working memory. The sensory cortex processes and interprets sensory information, with different subareas dedicated to different senses, like the visual and the auditory areas. A central function of the hippocampus is the formation and retrieval of long-term memories. It belongs to the limbic system, which plays a key role in the regulation of emotions through the amygdala. The motor cortex is responsible for planning, executing, and controlling voluntary movements. Broca's area is a separate region dedicated to speech production. The activity of the different areas is additionally influenced by neurotransmitters, which are signaling molecules that enhance or inhibit different types of neural communication. For example, dopamine influences motivation and pleasure while serotonin affects mood and appetite.
The close interrelation of brain processes and the mind is seen by the effect that physical changes of the brain have on the mind. For instance, the consumption of psychoactive drugs, like caffeine, antidepressants, alcohol, and psychedelics, temporarily affects brain chemistry with diverse effects on the mind, ranging from increased attention to mood changes, impaired cognitive functions, and hallucinations. Long-term changes to the brain in the form of neurodegenerative diseases and brain injuries can lead to permanent alterations in mental functions. Alzheimer's disease in its first stage deteriorates the hippocampus, reducing the ability to form new memories and recall existing ones. An often-cited case of the effects of brain injury is Phineas Gage, whose prefrontal cortex was severely damaged during a work accident when an iron rod pierced through his skull and brain. Gage survived the accident but his personality and social attitude changed significantly as he became more impulsive, irritable, and anti-social while showing little regard for social conventions and an impaired ability to plan and make rational decisions. Not all these changes were permanent and Gage managed to recover and adapt in some areas.
Minimal forms of information processing are already found in the earliest forms of life 4 to 3.5 billion years ago, like the abilities of bacteria and eukaryotic unicellular organisms to sense the environment, store this information, and react to it. Nerve cells emerged with the development of multicellular organisms more than 600 million years ago as a way to process and transmit information. About 600 to 550 million years ago, an evolutionary bifurcation happened into radially symmetric organisms with ring-shaped nervous systems or a nerve net, like jellyfish, and organisms with bilaterally symmetric bodies, whose nervous systems tend to be more centralized. About 540 million years ago, vertebrates evolved within the group of bilaterally organized organisms. Vertebrates, like birds and mammals, have a central nervous system including a complex brain with specialized functions. Invertebrates, like clams and insects, typically either have no or relatively simple brains. In the course of evolution, the brains of vertebrates tended to grow and the specialization of different brain areas tended to increase. These developments are closely related to changes in limb structures, sense organs, and living conditions with a close correspondence between the size of a brain area and the importance of its function to the organism. An important step in the evolution of mammals about 200 million years ago was the development of the neocortex, which is responsible for many higher-order brain functions.
The size of the brain relative to the body further increased with the development of primates, like monkeys, about 65 million years ago and later with the emergence of the first hominins about 7–5 million years ago. Anatomically modern humans appeared about 300,000 to 200,000 years ago. Various theories of the evolutionary processes responsible for human intelligence have been proposed. The social intelligence hypothesis says that the evolution of the human mind was triggered by the increased importance of social life and its emphasis on mental abilities associated with empathy, knowledge transfer, and meta-cognition. According to the ecological intelligence hypothesis, the main value of the increased mental capacities comes from their advantages in dealing with a complex physical environment through processes like behavioral flexibility, learning, and tool use. Other suggested mechanisms include the effects of a changed diet with energy-rich food and general benefits from an increased speed and efficiency of information processing. Some models propose that another major cognitive shift occurred possibly 50,000 to 40,000 years ago. Called behavioral modernity, it is associated with the emergence of new or improved mental abilities, such as technological innovativeness, abstract thinking, the use of symbols, planning, and social coordination.
Psychological transformations during adolescence are provoked by physiological developments and by being confronted with a different social situation in the form of new expectations from others. An important factor in this period is change to the self-concept, which can take the form of an identity crisis. This process typically involves developing individuality and independence from parents while at the same time seeking closeness and conformity with friends and peers. Further developments in this period include improvements to the reasoning ability and the formation of a principled moral viewpoint.
The mind also changes during adulthood but in a less rapid and pronounced manner. Reasoning and problem-solving skills improve during early and middle adulthood. Some people experience the mid-life transition as a midlife crisis involving an inner conflict about personal identity, associated with anxiety, a sense of a lack of accomplishments in life, or an awareness of mortality. Intellectual faculties tend to decline in later adulthood, specifically the ability to learn complex unfamiliar tasks and later also the ability to remember. At the same time, people tend to become more inward-looking and cautious.
It is commonly acknowledged today that animals have some form of mind, but it is controversial to which animals this applies and how their mind differs from the human mind. Different conceptions of the mind lead to different responses to this problem. When understood in a very wide sense as the capacity to process information, the mind is present in all forms of life, including insects, plants, and individual cells. On the other side of the spectrum are views that deny the existence of mentality in most or all non-human animals based on the idea that they lack key mental capacities, like abstract rationality and symbolic language. The status of animal minds is highly relevant to the field of ethics since it affects the treatment of animals, including the topic of animal rights.
Discontinuity views state that the minds of non-human animals are fundamentally different from human minds and often point to higher mental faculties, like thinking, reasoning, and deliberate decision-making. This outlook is reflected in the traditionally influential position of defining humans as "rational animals" as opposed to all other animals. Continuity views, by contrast, emphasize similarities and see cognitive differences in degree rather than kind. Central considerations for this position are the shared evolutionary origin and organic similarities on the level of the brain and nervous system. Observable behavior is another key factor, such as problem-solving skills, animal communication, and reactions to and expressions of pain and pleasure. Of particular importance are the questions of consciousness and sentience, that is, to what extent non-human animals have a subjective experience of the world and are capable of suffering and feeling joy.
Some of the difficulties of assessing animal minds are also reflected in the topic of artificial minds. It includes the question of whether computer systems implementing artificial intelligence should be considered a form of mind. This idea is consistent with some theories of the nature of mind, such as functionalism and its claim that mental concepts describe functional roles. It asserts that the functions implemented by biological brains could in principle also be implemented by artificial devices.
There is a great variety of mental disorders, each associated with a different form of malfunctioning. Anxiety disorders involve intense and persistent fear that is disproportionate to the actual threat and significantly impairs everyday life. An example is social phobia, which involves irrational fear of certain social situations. Anxiety disorders also include obsessive–compulsive disorder, for which the anxiety manifests in the form of intrusive thoughts that the person tries to alleviate by following compulsive rituals. Mood disorders cause intense moods or mood swings that are inconsistent with the external circumstances and can last for long periods. For instance, people affected by bipolar disorder experience extreme mood swings between manic states of euphoria and depressive states of hopelessness. Personality disorders are characterized by enduring patterns of maladaptive behavior that significantly impair regular life. Paranoid personality disorder, for example, leads people to be deeply suspicious of the motives of others without rational basis. Psychotic disorders are among the most severe mental illnesses and involve a distorted relation to reality in the form of hallucinations and delusions, as seen in schizophrenia. Other disorders include dissociative disorders and eating disorders.
Various fields of inquiry study the mind, including psychology, neuroscience, philosophy, and cognitive science. They differ from each other in the aspects of mind they investigate and the methods they employ. The study of the mind poses various problems since it is difficult to directly examine, manipulate, and measure it. Trying to circumvent this problem by investigating the brain comes with new challenges of its own, mainly because of the brain's complexity as a neural network consisting of billions of neurons, each with up to 10,000 links to other neurons.
Psychology is the scientific study of mind and behavior. It investigates conscious and unconscious mental phenomena, including perception, memory, feeling, thought, decision, intelligence, and personality. It is further interested in their outward manifestation in the form of observable behavioral patterns, studying how these patterns depend on external circumstances and are shaped by learning. Psychology is a wide discipline that includes many subfields. Cognitive psychology is interested in higher-order mental activities like thinking, problem-solving, reasoning, and concept formation. Biological psychology seeks to understand the underlying mechanisms on the physiological level and how they depend on genetic transmission and the environment. Developmental psychology studies the development of the mind from childhood to old age while social psychology examines the influence of social contexts on mind and behavior. Personality psychology investigates personality, exploring how characteristic patterns of thought, feeling, and behavior develop and vary among individuals. Further subfields include comparative, clinical, educational, occupational, and neuropsychology. As a scientific discipline, psychology emerged at the end of the 19th century from the experimental work of Wilhelm Wundt (1832–1920). Early schools of thought included structuralism, psychoanalysis, Gestalt psychology, functionalism, and behaviorism.
Psychologists use a great variety of methods to study the mind. Experimental approaches set up a controlled situation, either in the laboratory or the field, in which they modify independent variables and measure their effects on dependent variables. This approach makes it possible to identify causal relations between the variables. For example, to determine whether people with similar interests (independent variable) are more likely to become friends (dependent variable), participants in a study could be paired with either similar or dissimilar participants. After giving the pairs time to interact, it is assessed whether the members of similar pairs have more positive attitudes toward one another than the members of dissimilar pairs.
In modern neuroscience, neuroimaging techniques are of particular importance as the main research methods of neuroscientists. Functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) measures changes in the magnetic field of the brain associated with blood flow. Areas of increased blood flow indicate that the corresponding brain region is particularly active. Positron emission tomography (PET) uses radioactive substances to detect a range of metabolic changes in the brain. Electroencephalography (EEG) measures the electrical activity of the brain, usually by placing electrodes on the scalp and measuring the voltage differences between them. These techniques are often employed to measure brain changes under particular circumstances, for example, while engaged in a specific cognitive task. Important insights are also gained from patients and laboratory animals with brain damage, helping neuroscientists understand the function of the damaged area and how its absence affects the remaining brain.
Philosophy of mind examines the nature of mental phenomena and their relation to the physical world. It seeks to understand the "mark of the mental", that is, the features that all mental states have in common. It further investigates the essence of different types of mental phenomena, such as beliefs, desires, emotions, intentionality, and consciousness while exploring how they are related to one another. Philosophy of mind also examines solutions to the mind–body problem, like dualism, idealism, and physicalism, and assesses arguments for and against them. It asks whether people have a free will or the ability to choose their actions, and how this ability contrasts with the idea that everything is determined by preceding causes.
While philosophers of mind also include empirical considerations in their inquiry, they differ from fields like psychology and neuroscience by giving significantly more emphasis to non-empirical forms of inquiry. One such method is conceptual analysis, which aims to clarify the meaning of concepts, like mind and intention, by decomposing them to identify their semantic parts. Thought experiments are often used to evoke intuitions about abstract theories to assess their coherence and plausibility. To do so, philosophers imagine a situation relevant to a theory and employ counterfactual thinking to assess the possible consequences of this theory. Influential thought experiments include Mary the color scientist, philosophical zombies, and brain in a vat-scenarios. Because of the subjective nature of the mind, the phenomenological method is also commonly used to analyze the structure of consciousness by describing experience from the first-person perspective. The philosophical discussion of the mind has a long history, reaching back to antiquity. Influential contributions were made by Plato (c. 428–347 BCE), Aristotle (384–322 BCE), René Descartes (1596–1650), David Hume (1711–1776), Immanuel Kant (1724–1804), William James (1842–1910), and Gilbert Ryle (1900–1976).
Cognitive science is the interdisciplinary study of mental representations and processes. It aims to overcome the challenge of understanding something as complex as the mind by integrating research from diverse fields ranging from psychology and neuroscience to philosophy, linguistics, and artificial intelligence. Unlike these disciplines, it is not a unified field but a collaborative effort. One difficulty in synthesizing their insights is that each of these disciplines explores the mind from a different perspective and level of abstraction while using different research methods to arrive at its conclusion. Cognitive science emerged in the second half of the 20th century as researchers from various disciplines began to examine how mental processes represent the world and transform information. The field expanded in the 1980s following advances in neuroimaging to include a biological perspective on how computational processes are implemented by the brain.
To incorporate insights from diverse disciplines, cognitive science relies on a unified conceptualization of minds as information processors. This means that mental processes are understood as computations that retrieve, transform, store, and transmit information. For example, perception retrieves sensory information from the environment and transforms it to extract meaningful patterns that can be used in other mental processes, such as planning and decision-making. Cognitive science relies on different levels of description to analyze cognitive processes. The most abstract level focuses on the basic problem the process is supposed to solve and the reasons why the organism needs to solve it. The intermediate level seeks to uncover the algorithm as a formal step-by-step procedure to solve the problem. The most concrete level asks how the algorithm is implemented through physiological changes on the level of the brain. Another methodology is to analyze the mind as a complex system composed of individual subsystems that can be studied independently of one another.
Kim 2011, pp. 2, 6American Psychological Association 2018, § MindHarperCollins 2022, § MindHarperCollins 2024Morton 2005, p. 603Paivio 2014, pp. vi–vii - Kim, Jaegwon (2011). Philosophy of Mind (3rd ed.). Westview Press. ISBN 978-0-8133-4458-4.
Sharov 2012, pp. 343–344Carruthers 2019, pp. ix, 29–30Griffin 1998, pp. 53–55 - Sharov, Alexei A. (2012). "Minimal Mind". In Swan, Liz (ed.). Origins of Mind. Springer. pp. 343–360. ISBN 978-94-007-5419-5. https://books.google.com/books?id=oQ5HAAAAQBAJ&pg=PA343
Stich & Warfield 2008, pp. ix–x - Stich, Stephen P.; Warfield, Ted A. (2008). "Introduction". In Stich, Stephen P.; Warfield, Ted A. (eds.). The Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind. John Wiley & Sons. pp. vii–xi. ISBN 978-0-470-99875-5. https://books.google.com/books?id=NEGK_ZStddkC&pg=PR7
Pashler 2013, pp. xxix–xxxFriedenberg, Silverman & Spivey 2022, pp. 14–17 - Pashler, Harold (2013). "Introduction". In Pashler, Harold (ed.). Encyclopedia of the Mind. Sage. pp. xxix–xxxi. ISBN 978-1-4129-5057-2. https://books.google.com/books?id=lu3aMe6kRowC
American Psychological Association 2018, § Mind, § PsycheMerriam-Webster 2024, § MentalityKim 2011, p. 7 - American Psychological Association (2018). "APA Dictionary of Psychology". American Psychological Association. https://dictionary.apa.org
HarperCollins 2022, § SoulKim 2011, pp. 5, 31Swinburne 1998, Lead Section - HarperCollins (2022). "The American Heritage Dictionary". HarperCollins. Retrieved 9 May 2024. https://www.ahdictionary.com
HarperCollins 2022, § SpiritMerriam-Webster 2024, § Spirit - HarperCollins (2022). "The American Heritage Dictionary". HarperCollins. Retrieved 9 May 2024. https://www.ahdictionary.com
HarperCollins 2022, § CognitionBermúdez 2014, p. 16 - HarperCollins (2022). "The American Heritage Dictionary". HarperCollins. Retrieved 9 May 2024. https://www.ahdictionary.com
HarperCollins 2022, § IntellectMerriam-Webster 2024, § Intellect - HarperCollins (2022). "The American Heritage Dictionary". HarperCollins. Retrieved 9 May 2024. https://www.ahdictionary.com
Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 273–274Nairne 2011, p. 312Merriam-Webster 2024, § Intelligence - Bernstein, Douglas; Nash, Peggy W. (2006). Essentials of Psychology. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. ISBN 978-0-618-71312-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=4Do-bFrt9tUC
American Psychological Association 2018, § MindUttal 2020, pp. 96–97Jaworski 2011, p. 4 - American Psychological Association (2018). "APA Dictionary of Psychology". American Psychological Association. https://dictionary.apa.org
Hoad 1993, p. 294Smith 1996, p. 105Cresswell 2010, p. 275Weekley 2012, p. 931Giannopulu 2019, p. 6 - Hoad, T. F. (1993). The Concise Oxford Dictionary of English Etymology. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-283098-2.
Not all languages have a word that directly corresponds to the English word mind. For example, German uses the word Geist, which can mean both 'mind' or 'spirit'.[13] /wiki/German_language
Sharov 2012, pp. 343–344Pashler 2013, pp. xxix–xxxPaivio 2014, pp. vi–viiVanderwolf 2013, p. 155 - Sharov, Alexei A. (2012). "Minimal Mind". In Swan, Liz (ed.). Origins of Mind. Springer. pp. 343–360. ISBN 978-94-007-5419-5. https://books.google.com/books?id=oQ5HAAAAQBAJ&pg=PA343
Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 85–86, 123–125Martin 1998, Lead sectionGross 2020, pp. 74–76 - Bernstein, Douglas; Nash, Peggy W. (2006). Essentials of Psychology. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. ISBN 978-0-618-71312-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=4Do-bFrt9tUC
Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 208–209, 241American Psychological Association 2018, § Memory - Bernstein, Douglas; Nash, Peggy W. (2006). Essentials of Psychology. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. ISBN 978-0-618-71312-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=4Do-bFrt9tUC
Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 210, 241Tulving 2001, p. 278Tsien 2005, p. 861Campbell & Barohn 2019, p. 94 - Bernstein, Douglas; Nash, Peggy W. (2006). Essentials of Psychology. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. ISBN 978-0-618-71312-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=4Do-bFrt9tUC
Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 214–217, 241Tsien 2005, p. 861Khurana & Khurana 2018, p. 462 - Bernstein, Douglas; Nash, Peggy W. (2006). Essentials of Psychology. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. ISBN 978-0-618-71312-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=4Do-bFrt9tUC
Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 249, 290Ball 2013, pp. 739–740 - Bernstein, Douglas; Nash, Peggy W. (2006). Essentials of Psychology. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. ISBN 978-0-618-71312-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=4Do-bFrt9tUC
Nunes 2011, p. 2066Groarke, § 9. The SyllogismBall 2013, pp. 739–740Bernstein & Nash 2006, p. 254Chowdhary 2020, p. 27 - Nunes, Terezinha (2011). "Logical Reasoning and Learning". In Seel, Norbert M. (ed.). Encyclopedia of the Sciences of Learning. Springer. pp. 2066–2069. ISBN 978-1-4419-1427-9. https://books.google.com/books?id=xZuSxo4JxoAC
Ball 2013, pp. 739–740Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 257–258, 290–291 - Ball, Linden J. (2013). "Thinking". In Pashler, Harold (ed.). Encyclopedia of the Mind. Sage. pp. 739–742. ISBN 978-1-4129-5057-2. https://books.google.com/books?id=lu3aMe6kRowC
Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 265–266, 291 - Bernstein, Douglas; Nash, Peggy W. (2006). Essentials of Psychology. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. ISBN 978-0-618-71312-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=4Do-bFrt9tUC
Bernstein & Nash 2006, p. 269Rescorla 2023, Lead SectionAydede 2017 - Bernstein, Douglas; Nash, Peggy W. (2006). Essentials of Psychology. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. ISBN 978-0-618-71312-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=4Do-bFrt9tUC
Singer 2000, pp. 227–228Kind 2017, Lead SectionAmerican Psychological Association 2018, § ImaginationHoff 2020, pp. 617–618 - Singer, Jerome L. (2000). "Imagination". In Kazdin, Alan E. (ed.). Encyclopedia of Psychology. Vol. 4. American Psychological Association. pp. 227–230. ISBN 978-1-55798-187-5.
Weiner 2000, pp. 314–315Helms 2000, lead sectionBernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 298, 336–337Müller 1996, p. 14 - Weiner, Bernard (2000). "Motivation: An Overview". In Kazdin, Alan E. (ed.). Encyclopedia of Psychology. Vol. 5. American Psychological Association. pp. 314–317. ISBN 978-1-55798-187-5.
Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 322–323, 337American Psychological Association 2018, § Emotion - Bernstein, Douglas; Nash, Peggy W. (2006). Essentials of Psychology. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. ISBN 978-0-618-71312-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=4Do-bFrt9tUC
Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 126–127, 131American Psychological Association 2018, § AttentionMcPeek 2009, Attention: Physiological - Bernstein, Douglas; Nash, Peggy W. (2006). Essentials of Psychology. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. ISBN 978-0-618-71312-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=4Do-bFrt9tUC
Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 171, 202American Psychological Association 2018, § Learning - Bernstein, Douglas; Nash, Peggy W. (2006). Essentials of Psychology. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. ISBN 978-0-618-71312-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=4Do-bFrt9tUC
Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 137–138Davies 2001, pp. 190–192Gennaro, Lead Section, § 1. Terminological Matters: Various Concepts of Consciousness - Bernstein, Douglas; Nash, Peggy W. (2006). Essentials of Psychology. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. ISBN 978-0-618-71312-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=4Do-bFrt9tUC
Davies 2001, pp. 191–192Smithies 2019, pp. 83–84Gennaro, § 1. Terminological Matters: Various Concepts of Consciousness - Davies, Martin (2001). "Consciousness". In Wilson, Robert A.; Keil, Frank C. (eds.). The MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences (MITECS). MIT Press. pp. 190–193. ISBN 978-0-262-73144-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=-wt1aZrGXLYC&pg=PA191
Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 137–138Kihlstrom & Tobias 1991, p. 212American Psychological Association 2018, § Unconscious - Bernstein, Douglas; Nash, Peggy W. (2006). Essentials of Psychology. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. ISBN 978-0-618-71312-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=4Do-bFrt9tUC
The precise differences between these concepts are disputed. In Freud's psychoanalysis, the preconscious mind lies outside current awareness but can easily be accessed, whereas the unconscious mind is further removed from deliberate access. The word subconscious is sometimes used as a synonym of preconscious.[32]
Gennaro, Lead Section, § 1. Terminological Matters: Various Concepts of ConsciousnessKind 2023, § 2.1 Phenomenal Consciousness - Gennaro, Rocco J. "Consciousness". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 6 April 2024. Retrieved 19 April 2024. https://iep.utm.edu/consciousness/
Mijoia 2005, pp. 1818–1819Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 137–138Steinberg Gould 2020, p. 151American Psychological Association 2018, § UnconsciousCarel 2006, p. 176 - Mijoia, Alain de (2005). "The Unconscious". International Dictionary of Psychoanalysis. Macmillan Reference. pp. 1818–1820. ISBN 978-0-02-865927-5.
Kim 2005, pp. 607–608Swinburne 2013, pp. 72–73Lindeman, § 1. General Characterization of the Propositional Attitudes - Kim, Jaegwon (2005). "Mind, Problems of the Philosophy of". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. pp. 607–612. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7. Archived from the original on 11 April 2024. https://www.oxfordreference.com/display/10.1093/acref/9780199264797.001.0001/acref-9780199264797-e-1610
Some mental states, like perceptions and emotions, may have both qualitative and propositional aspects.[36]
Harman 2013, pp. 1–2Broome 2021, § 1. Normativity and Reasons, §2. The Meaning of "Rationality"Siegel 2017, p. 157Maruyama 2020, pp. 172–173 - Harman, Gilbert (2013). "Rationality". In Hugh, LaFollette (ed.). The International Encyclopedia of Ethics (1 ed.). Wiley. doi:10.1002/9781444367072.wbiee181. ISBN 978-1-4051-8641-4. Archived from the original on 14 August 2022. https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1002/9781444367072.wbiee181
Nolfi 2015, pp. 41–42Tappolet 2023, pp. 137–138Knauff & Spohn 2021, § 2.2 Basic Concepts of Rationality Assessment, § 4.2 Descriptive TheoriesVogler 2016, pp. 30–31 - Nolfi, Kate (2015). "Which Mental States Are Rationally Evaluable, And Why?". Philosophical Issues. 25 (1): 41–63. doi:10.1111/phis.12051. https://doi.org/10.1111%2Fphis.12051
Bartlett 2018, pp. 1, 4–5Schwitzgebel 2024, § 2.1 Occurrent Versus Dispositional BeliefWilkes 2012, p. 412 - Bartlett, Gary (2018). "Occurrent States". Canadian Journal of Philosophy. 48 (1): 1–17. doi:10.1080/00455091.2017.1323531. https://doi.org/10.1080%2F00455091.2017.1323531
Kenny 1992, pp. 71–72Perler 2015, pp. 3–6, 11Hufendiek & Wild 2015, pp. 264–265 - Kenny, Anthony (1992). "5. Abilities, Faculties, Powers, and Dispositions". The Metaphysics of Mind. pp. 66–85. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780192830708.003.0005. ISBN 978-0-19-167052-7. https://doi.org/10.1093%2Facprof%3Aoso%2F9780192830708.003.0005
Kenny 1992, p. 75Perler 2015, pp. 5–6 - Kenny, Anthony (1992). "5. Abilities, Faculties, Powers, and Dispositions". The Metaphysics of Mind. pp. 66–85. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780192830708.003.0005. ISBN 978-0-19-167052-7. https://doi.org/10.1093%2Facprof%3Aoso%2F9780192830708.003.0005
Kenny 1992, pp. 75–76Perler 2015, pp. 5–6 - Kenny, Anthony (1992). "5. Abilities, Faculties, Powers, and Dispositions". The Metaphysics of Mind. pp. 66–85. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780192830708.003.0005. ISBN 978-0-19-167052-7. https://doi.org/10.1093%2Facprof%3Aoso%2F9780192830708.003.0005
Kenny 1992, pp. 78–79Perler 2015, pp. 5–6McLear, § 1i. Sensibility, Understanding, and Reason - Kenny, Anthony (1992). "5. Abilities, Faculties, Powers, and Dispositions". The Metaphysics of Mind. pp. 66–85. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780192830708.003.0005. ISBN 978-0-19-167052-7. https://doi.org/10.1093%2Facprof%3Aoso%2F9780192830708.003.0005
Mental faculties also play a central role in the Indian tradition, such as the contrast between the sense mind (manas) and intellect (buddhi).[44] /wiki/Buddhi
Robbins 2017, Lead Section, § 1. What Is a Mental Module?Perler 2015, p. 7Hufendiek & Wild 2015, pp. 264–265Bermúdez 2014, p. 277 - Robbins, Philip (2017). "Modularity of Mind". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 12 February 2021. Retrieved 16 April 2024. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/modularity-mind/
Robbins 2017, § 1. What Is a Mental Module?Hufendiek & Wild 2015, pp. 265–268Bermúdez 2014, pp. 288–290 - Robbins, Philip (2017). "Modularity of Mind". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 12 February 2021. Retrieved 16 April 2024. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/modularity-mind/
A different perspective is proposed by the massive modularity hypothesis, which states that the mind is entirely composed of modules with high-level modules establishing the connection between low-level modules.[48]
Robbins 2017, § 1. What Is a Mental Module?Hufendiek & Wild 2015, pp. 266–267 - Robbins, Philip (2017). "Modularity of Mind". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 12 February 2021. Retrieved 16 April 2024. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/modularity-mind/
Robbins 2017, § 1. What Is a Mental Module?Bermúdez 2014, p. 289 - Robbins, Philip (2017). "Modularity of Mind". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 12 February 2021. Retrieved 16 April 2024. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/modularity-mind/
Olson 2013, p. 51Kim 2011, pp. 17–18O’Madagain, Lead SectionBayne 2022, pp. 8–9 - Olson, Eric T. (2013). "There Is No Problem of the Self". In Gallagher, Shaun; Shear, Jonathan (eds.). Models of the Self. Andrews UK Limited. pp. 49–62. ISBN 978-1-84540-723-0. https://books.google.com/books?id=T7W7BAAAQBAJ&pg=PT111
Kim 2011, pp. 18–20Bayne 2022, pp. 8–10Audi 1993, pp. 167–168 - Kim, Jaegwon (2011). Philosophy of Mind (3rd ed.). Westview Press. ISBN 978-0-8133-4458-4.
Kriegel 2014, p. 384Searle 1991, pp. 45–47, 50Gillett 1996, pp. 191–192 - Kriegel, Uriah (2014). "Intentionality". In Bayne, Tim; Cleeremans, Axel; Wilken, Patrick (eds.). The Oxford Companion to Consciousness. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-102103-9. https://books.google.com/books?id=ICf-AgAAQBAJ&pg=PA384
Intentionality is to be distinguished from intention in the sense of having a plan to perform a certain action.[54] /wiki/Intention#Intention_and_intentionality
O’Madagain, Lead SectionKriegel 2015, p. 141Kim 2011, pp. 23–25Kriegel 2014, pp. 383–384Crane 1998, pp. 229–230 - O’Madagain, Cathal. "Intentionality". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 28 April 2024. Retrieved 10 May 2024. https://iep.utm.edu/intentio/
Levin 2023, § 2.3 BehaviorismGraham 2023, § 1. What Is Behaviorism?, § 5. Why Be a BehavioristCunningham 2000, p. 40 - Levin, Janet (2023). "Functionalism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 18 April 2021. Retrieved 22 April 2024. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/functionalism/
Levin 2023, Lead Section, § 1. What Is Functionalism?Polger, Lead SectionCunningham 2000, p. 40 - Levin, Janet (2023). "Functionalism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 18 April 2021. Retrieved 22 April 2024. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/functionalism/
Rescorla 2020, Lead Section, § 3. The Classical Computational Theory of MindFriedenberg, Silverman & Spivey 2022, pp. 2–3Bermúdez 2014, pp. 3, 85 - Rescorla, Michael (2020). "The Computational Theory of Mind". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 18 December 2020. Retrieved 11 May 2024. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/computational-mind/
Rowlands, Lau & Deutsch 2020, Lead Section, § 1. IntroductionSmith, Lead Section - Rowlands, Mark; Lau, Joe; Deutsch, Max (2020). "Externalism About the Mind". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 13 April 2021. Retrieved 25 February 2024. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/content-externalism/
Rowlands, Lau & Deutsch 2020, § 1. Introduction, § 3. Content ExternalismSmith, § 1. Hilary Putnam and Natural Kind Externalism - Rowlands, Mark; Lau, Joe; Deutsch, Max (2020). "Externalism About the Mind". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 13 April 2021. Retrieved 25 February 2024. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/content-externalism/
Shapiro & Spaulding 2024, § 2.2 Embedded CognitionWeiskopf & Adams 2015, pp. 127–128 - Shapiro, Lawrence; Spaulding, Shannon (2024). "Embodied Cognition". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/embodied-cognition/
Rowlands, Lau & Deutsch 2020, § 1. Introduction, § 5. Extended MindGreif 2017, pp. 4311–4312Kiverstein, Farina & Clark 2013 - Rowlands, Mark; Lau, Joe; Deutsch, Max (2020). "Externalism About the Mind". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 13 April 2021. Retrieved 25 February 2024. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/content-externalism/
Rowlands, Lau & Deutsch 2020, § 7. Extended Mind and the 4E MindRowlands 2009, pp. 53–56 - Rowlands, Mark; Lau, Joe; Deutsch, Max (2020). "Externalism About the Mind". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 13 April 2021. Retrieved 25 February 2024. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/content-externalism/
Rowlands, Lau & Deutsch 2020, § 7. Extended Mind and the 4E MindShapiro & Spaulding 2024, § 2.1 Three Themes of Embodied CognitionShapiro 2019, pp. 5, 197–198 - Rowlands, Mark; Lau, Joe; Deutsch, Max (2020). "Externalism About the Mind". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 13 April 2021. Retrieved 25 February 2024. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/content-externalism/
More generally, embodied cognition is the study of the effects of bodily phenomena on the mind. It examines, for example, how certain bodily movements improve or hinder cognitive performance and how motor capacities affect the development of cognitive abilities.[65]
Kim 2005, p. 608Jaworski 2011, pp. 11–12Searle 2004, pp. 3–4 - Kim, Jaegwon (2005). "Mind, Problems of the Philosophy of". In Honderich, Ted (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy. Oxford University Press. pp. 607–612. ISBN 978-0-19-926479-7. Archived from the original on 11 April 2024. https://www.oxfordreference.com/display/10.1093/acref/9780199264797.001.0001/acref-9780199264797-e-1610
Westphal 2016, pp. 12–13, 21–22Crane & Patterson 2000, pp. 2–5 - Westphal, Jonathan (2016). The Mind-Body Problem. MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-52956-3. https://books.google.com/books?id=EY0nDQAAQBAJ&pg=PA12
According to Aristotle's hylomorphism, for example, they are complementary principles: the soul is the form of the body while the body is the matter of the soul.[68] /wiki/Aristotle
Kim 2011, pp. 2–3, 5–6Jaworski 2011, pp. 5–8, 68–69McQueen & McQueen 2010, p. 135Morton 2005, p. 603 - Kim, Jaegwon (2011). Philosophy of Mind (3rd ed.). Westview Press. ISBN 978-0-8133-4458-4.
Jaworski 2011, pp. 34–36Kim 2005, p. 608Searle 2004, pp. 13, 41–42Matheson 2017, p. 12 - Jaworski, William (2011). Philosophy of Mind: A Comprehensive Introduction (1 ed.). Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-1-4443-3367-1.
Jaworski 2011, pp. 5, 202–203Searle 2004, p. 44 - Jaworski, William (2011). Philosophy of Mind: A Comprehensive Introduction (1 ed.). Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-1-4443-3367-1.
Jaworski 2011, p. 5Searle 2004, pp. 44, 47–48 - Jaworski, William (2011). Philosophy of Mind: A Comprehensive Introduction (1 ed.). Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-1-4443-3367-1.
There are other forms of idealism that assert slightly different positions, such as transcendental idealism and absolute idealism.[74] /wiki/Transcendental_idealism
Jaworski 2011, p. 246 - Jaworski, William (2011). Philosophy of Mind: A Comprehensive Introduction (1 ed.). Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-1-4443-3367-1.
Jaworski 2011, p. 256 - Jaworski, William (2011). Philosophy of Mind: A Comprehensive Introduction (1 ed.). Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-1-4443-3367-1.
The two terms are usually treated as synonyms but some theorists distinguish them by holding that materialism is restricted to matter while physicalism is a wider term that includes additional physical phenomena, like forces.[77] /wiki/Matter
Jaworski 2011, p. 68Stoljar 2024, Lead SectionSearle 2004, p. 48Kind 2020, § 3. Physicalism - Jaworski, William (2011). Philosophy of Mind: A Comprehensive Introduction (1 ed.). Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-1-4443-3367-1.
Jaworski 2011, pp. 71–72Searle 2004, pp. 75–76 - Jaworski, William (2011). Philosophy of Mind: A Comprehensive Introduction (1 ed.). Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-1-4443-3367-1.
Jaworski 2011, pp. 72–73, 102–104Searle 2004, pp. 48–52 - Jaworski, William (2011). Philosophy of Mind: A Comprehensive Introduction (1 ed.). Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-1-4443-3367-1.
Ravenscroft 2005, p. 47Stoljar 2024, § 2.2.1 Type Physicalism - Ravenscroft, Ian (2005). Philosophy of Mind: A Beginner's Guide. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-925254-1. https://books.google.com/books?id=f1EAEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA47
Jaworski 2011, pp. 129–130Bigaj & Wüthrich 2015, p. 357 - Jaworski, William (2011). Philosophy of Mind: A Comprehensive Introduction (1 ed.). Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-1-4443-3367-1.
Levin 2023, Lead SectionSearle 2004, p. 62 - Levin, Janet (2023). "Functionalism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 18 April 2021. Retrieved 22 April 2024. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/functionalism/
Levin 2023, § 1. What Is Functionalism?Jaworski 2011, pp. 136–137 - Levin, Janet (2023). "Functionalism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 18 April 2021. Retrieved 22 April 2024. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/functionalism/
Grünberg 2007, p. 237Smith 2004, p. 124Priest 2002, p. 66 - Grünberg, David (2007). "Husserl's Transcendental Phenomenology and the Mind-body Problem". In Tymieniecka, Anna-Teresa (ed.). Phenomenology of Life - From the Animal Soul to the Human Mind: Book II. The Human Soul in the Creative Transformation of the Mind. Springer. pp. 237–258. ISBN 978-1-4020-5182-1. https://books.google.com/books?id=44YzwTjH2goC&pg=PA237
Weisberg, Lead Section, § 1. Stating the ProblemBlackmore 2013, pp. 33–35Searle 2004, pp. 39–40 - Weisberg, Josh. "Hard Problem of Consciousness". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 19 July 2023. Retrieved 22 April 2024. https://iep.utm.edu/hard-problem-of-conciousness/
Opris et al. 2017, pp. 69–70Barrett 2009, pp. 326–327 - Opris, Ioan; Casanova, Manuel F.; Lebedev, Mikhail A.; Popescu, Aurel I. (2017). "Prefrontal Cortical Microcircuits Support the Emergence of Mind". In Opris, Ioan (ed.). The Physics of the Mind and Brain Disorders: Integrated Neural Circuits Supporting the Emergence of Mind. Springer. pp. 69–94. ISBN 978-3-319-29672-2.
Popescu & Opris 2017, pp. 23–24Scanlon & Sanders 2018, p. 178Yukalov & Sornette 2014, p. 38Pal 2021, pp. 145 - Popescu, Aurel I.; Opris, Ioan (2017). "Introduction: From Neurons to the Mind". In Opris, Ioan (ed.). The Physics of the Mind and Brain Disorders: Integrated Neural Circuits Supporting the Emergence of Mind. Springer. pp. 23–54. ISBN 978-3-319-29672-2.
Athreya & Mouza 2016, pp. 52–53Schoenberg, Marsh & Lerner 2011, p. 60Benarroch 2021, pp. 437–438 - Athreya, Balu H.; Mouza, Chrystalla (2016). Thinking Skills for the Digital Generation: The Development of Thinking and Learning in the Age of Information. Springer. ISBN 978-3-319-12364-6. https://books.google.com/books?id=Uc3BDQAAQBAJ&pg=PA52
American Psychological Association 2018, § BrainSchoenberg, Marsh & Lerner 2011, p. 66 - American Psychological Association (2018). "APA Dictionary of Psychology". American Psychological Association. https://dictionary.apa.org
Sanderson & Huffman 2019, pp. 59–61Saab 2009, pp. 1–2Scanlon & Sanders 2018, pp. 178–180 - Sanderson, Catherine A.; Huffman, Karen R. (2019). Real World Psychology. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-119-57775-1. https://books.google.com/books?id=gmfDDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA59
Athreya & Mouza 2016, pp. 52–53Opris et al. 2017, p. 70Schoenberg, Marsh & Lerner 2011, pp. 69–72 - Athreya, Balu H.; Mouza, Chrystalla (2016). Thinking Skills for the Digital Generation: The Development of Thinking and Learning in the Age of Information. Springer. ISBN 978-3-319-12364-6. https://books.google.com/books?id=Uc3BDQAAQBAJ&pg=PA52
Athreya & Mouza 2016, pp. 52–53Schoenberg, Marsh & Lerner 2011, pp. 76–77Benarroch 2021, pp. 437–438 - Athreya, Balu H.; Mouza, Chrystalla (2016). Thinking Skills for the Digital Generation: The Development of Thinking and Learning in the Age of Information. Springer. ISBN 978-3-319-12364-6. https://books.google.com/books?id=Uc3BDQAAQBAJ&pg=PA52
Reisyan 2015, pp. 91–92American Psychological Association 2018, § NeurotransmitterKhushboo, Kumar & Sharma 2020, p. 116 - Reisyan, Garo D. (2015). Neuro-Organizational Culture: A New Approach to Understanding Human Behavior and Interaction in the Workplace. Springer. ISBN 978-3-319-22147-2. https://books.google.com/books?id=k_3NCgAAQBAJ&pg=PA91
Winkelman 2011, p. 24Meyer et al. 2022, p. 27Frankish & Kasmirli 2009, p. 107Bunge 2014, p. 18 - Winkelman, Michael J. (2011). "A Paradigm for Understanding Altered Consciousness: The Integrative Mode of Consciousness". In Cardeña, Etzel; Winkelman, Michael J. (eds.). Altering Consciousness: Multidisciplinary Perspectives. Greenwood Publishing Group. pp. 23–44. ISBN 978-0-313-38309-0. https://books.google.com/books?id=SxfOEAAAQBAJ&pg=RA1-PA24
Dash & Villemarette-Pitman 2005, pp. 30–31Turkington & Mitchell 2010, p. 115 - Dash, Paul; Villemarette-Pitman, Nicole (2005). Alzheimer's Disease. Demos Medical Publishing. ISBN 978-1-934559-49-9. https://books.google.com/books?id=M1jSCgAAQBAJ&pg=PA30
Macmillan & Lena 2010, pp. 641–643Marsh et al. 2007, p. 44 - Macmillan, Malcolm; Lena, Matthew L. (2010). "Rehabilitating Phineas Gage". Neuropsychological Rehabilitation. 20 (5): 641–658. doi:10.1080/09602011003760527. PMID 20480430. https://doi.org/10.1080%2F09602011003760527
Macmillan & Lena 2010, p. 655 - Macmillan, Malcolm; Lena, Matthew L. (2010). "Rehabilitating Phineas Gage". Neuropsychological Rehabilitation. 20 (5): 641–658. doi:10.1080/09602011003760527. PMID 20480430. https://doi.org/10.1080%2F09602011003760527
Roth 2013, p. 3 - Roth, Gerhard (2013). The Long Evolution of Brains and Minds. Springer. ISBN 978-94-007-6258-9.
Hatfield 2013, pp. 3–4 - Hatfield, Gary (2013). "Introduction: The Evolution of Mind, Brain, and Culture". In Hatfield, Gary; Pittman, Holly (eds.). Evolution of Mind, Brain, and Culture. University of Pennsylvania Museum of Archaeology and Anthropology. pp. 1–44. ISBN 978-1-934536-49-0.
Hatfield 2013, pp. 4–5Roth 2013, pp. 3–4 - Hatfield, Gary (2013). "Introduction: The Evolution of Mind, Brain, and Culture". In Hatfield, Gary; Pittman, Holly (eds.). Evolution of Mind, Brain, and Culture. University of Pennsylvania Museum of Archaeology and Anthropology. pp. 1–44. ISBN 978-1-934536-49-0.
They include cnidarians and ctenophorans.[102] /wiki/Cnidarians
Roth 2013, pp. 265–266Erulkar & Lentz 2024, § Evolution and Development of the Nervous SystemHatfield 2013, pp. 6–7 - Roth, Gerhard (2013). The Long Evolution of Brains and Minds. Springer. ISBN 978-94-007-6258-9.
Erulkar & Lentz 2024, § Evolution and Development of the Nervous SystemHatfield 2013, p. 13 - Erulkar, Solomon D.; Lentz, Thomas L. (2024). "Nervous System". Encyclopædia Britannica. Archived from the original on 13 June 2015. Retrieved 2 May 2024. https://www.britannica.com/science/nervous-system
Aboitiz & Montiel 2007, p. 7Aboitiz & Montiel 2012, pp. 14–15Finlay, Innocenti & Scheich 2013, p. 3Jerison 2013, pp. 7–8 - Aboitiz, F.; Montiel, J. F. (2007). Origin and Evolution of the Vertebrate Telencephalon, with Special Reference to the Mammalian Neocortex. Springer. ISBN 978-3-540-49761-5. https://books.google.com/books?id=N4HB0Sw-4u8C&pg=PA7
Hatfield 2013, pp. 6–8Reyes & Sherwood 2014, p. 12Wragg-Sykes 2016, p. 183 - Hatfield, Gary (2013). "Introduction: The Evolution of Mind, Brain, and Culture". In Hatfield, Gary; Pittman, Holly (eds.). Evolution of Mind, Brain, and Culture. University of Pennsylvania Museum of Archaeology and Anthropology. pp. 1–44. ISBN 978-1-934536-49-0.
Hatfield 2013, p. 9Wragg-Sykes 2016, p. 183Fagan & Durrani 2021, 3. Enter Homo Sapiens (c. 300,000 Years Ago and Later) - Hatfield, Gary (2013). "Introduction: The Evolution of Mind, Brain, and Culture". In Hatfield, Gary; Pittman, Holly (eds.). Evolution of Mind, Brain, and Culture. University of Pennsylvania Museum of Archaeology and Anthropology. pp. 1–44. ISBN 978-1-934536-49-0.
Roth 2013, p. 3Hatfield 2013, pp. 36–43Mandalaywala, Fleener & Maestripieri 2014, pp. 28–29 - Roth, Gerhard (2013). The Long Evolution of Brains and Minds. Springer. ISBN 978-94-007-6258-9.
Majkić 2024, pp. 97–99Sterelny 2011, pp. 809, 811–812 - Majkić, Ana (2024). "Behavioral Modernity, Evolutionary Synergies, and the Symbolic Species". In Gontier, Nathalie; Lock, Andy; Sinha, Chris (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Human Symbolic Evolution. Oxford University Press. pp. 97–132. ISBN 978-0-19-881378-1. https://books.google.com/books?id=4dPrEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA97
Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 171, 202, 342–343, 384Gross 2020, pp. 171–172, 184Nairne 2011, pp. 131–132, 240 - Bernstein, Douglas; Nash, Peggy W. (2006). Essentials of Psychology. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. ISBN 978-0-618-71312-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=4Do-bFrt9tUC
Yeomans & Arnold 2013, p. 31Oakley 2004, p. 1Nairne 2011, pp. 131–132 - Yeomans, Jane; Arnold, Christopher (2013). "Child Development". Teaching, Learning and Psychology. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-135-05633-9. https://books.google.com/books?id=mDL1eR1VrcIC&pg=PT31
Coall et al. 2015, pp. 57–58Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 345–346Abel 2003, pp. 231–232 - Coall, David A.; Callan, Anna C.; Dickins, Thomas E.; Chisholm, James S. (2015). "Evolution and Prenatal Development: An Evolutionary Perspective". In Lamb, Michael E. (ed.). Handbook of Child Psychology and Developmental Science, Socioemotional Processes. John Wiley & Sons. pp. 57–105. ISBN 978-1-118-95387-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=Fg3QBwAAQBAJ&pg=PA57
Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 342–344, 347–348, 384Packer 2017, pp. 7–8Smitsman & Corbetta 2011, Action in Infancy – Perspectives, Concepts, and ChallengesNairne 2011, pp. 131–132 - Bernstein, Douglas; Nash, Peggy W. (2006). Essentials of Psychology. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. ISBN 978-0-618-71312-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=4Do-bFrt9tUC
Packer 2017, pp. 7–8Freeman 1975, p. 114Driscoll & Easterbrooks 2007, p. 256Bernstein & Nash 2006, p. 384 - Packer, Martin J. (2017). Child Development: Understanding A Cultural Perspective. Sage. ISBN 978-1-5264-1311-6. https://books.google.com/books?id=V5NBDgAAQBAJ&pg=PA7
Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 349–350Gross 2020, pp. 566–572Khatoon 2012, pp. 308–311 - Bernstein, Douglas; Nash, Peggy W. (2006). Essentials of Psychology. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. ISBN 978-0-618-71312-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=4Do-bFrt9tUC
Bernstein & Nash 2006, p. 384Harrell 2018, pp. 478–479 - Bernstein, Douglas; Nash, Peggy W. (2006). Essentials of Psychology. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. ISBN 978-0-618-71312-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=4Do-bFrt9tUC
Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 384–385Gross 2020, pp. 619–620, 625–626Berman, Weems & Stickle 2006, pp. 285–292Nairne 2011, pp. 124–125, 131–132 - Bernstein, Douglas; Nash, Peggy W. (2006). Essentials of Psychology. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. ISBN 978-0-618-71312-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=4Do-bFrt9tUC
Bernstein & Nash 2006, p. 385Gross 2020, pp. 633–638, 664Nairne 2011, pp. 124–125, 131–132 - Bernstein, Douglas; Nash, Peggy W. (2006). Essentials of Psychology. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. ISBN 978-0-618-71312-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=4Do-bFrt9tUC
Carruthers 2019, pp. ix, 29–30Griffin 1998, pp. 53–55 - Carruthers, Peter (2019). Human and Animal Minds: The Consciousness Questions Laid to Rest (1 ed.). Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-884370-2.
Spradlin & Porterfield 2012, pp. 17–18 - Spradlin, W. W.; Porterfield, P. B. (2012). The Search for Certainty. Springer. ISBN 978-1-4612-5212-2. https://books.google.com/books?id=aynUBwAAQBAJ&pg=PA17
Carruthers 2019, pp. 29–30Steiner 2014, p. 93Thomas 2020, pp. 999–1000 - Carruthers, Peter (2019). Human and Animal Minds: The Consciousness Questions Laid to Rest (1 ed.). Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-884370-2.
Griffin 2013, p. ixCarruthers 2019, p. ixFischer 2021, pp. 28–29 - Griffin, Donald R. (2013). Animal Minds: Beyond Cognition to Consciousness. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-22712-2. https://books.google.com/books?id=K2uXAwAAQBAJ&pg=PR9
Fischer 2021, pp. 30–32Lurz, Lead SectionCarruthers 2019, pp. ix, 29–30Penn, Holyoak & Povinelli 2008, pp. 109–110 - Fischer, Bob (2021). Animal Ethics: A Contemporary Introduction. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-138-48440-5.
Melis & Monsó 2023, pp. 1–2Rysiew 2012 - Melis, Giacomo; Monsó, Susana (2023). "Are Humans the Only Rational Animals?". The Philosophical Quarterly. 74 (3): 844–864. doi:10.1093/pq/pqad090. https://doi.org/10.1093%2Fpq%2Fpqad090
Fischer 2021, pp. 32–35Lurz, Lead SectionGriffin 1998, pp. 53–55Carruthers 2019, pp. ix–xPenn, Holyoak & Povinelli 2008, pp. 109–110 - Fischer, Bob (2021). Animal Ethics: A Contemporary Introduction. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-138-48440-5.
McClelland 2021, p. 81Franklin 1995, pp. 1–2Anderson & Piccinini 2024, pp. 232–233Carruthers 2004, pp. 267–268 - McClelland, Tom (2021). What Is Philosophy of Mind?. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-5095-3878-2. https://books.google.com/books?id=viQqEAAAQBAJ&pg=PT81
Carruthers 2004, pp. 267–268Levin 2023, Lead Section, § 1. What Is Functionalism?Searle 2004, p. 62Jaworski 2011, pp. 136–137 - Carruthers, Peter (2004). The Nature of the Mind: An Introduction (1 ed.). Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-29994-7.
Biever 2023, pp. 686–689Carruthers 2004, pp. 248–249, 269–270Bansal 2022, § 6. The Plastic MindHodges 2013, pp. 3, 6 - Biever, Celeste (2023). "ChatGPT Broke the Turing Test — the Race Is on for New Ways to Assess AI". Nature. 619 (7971): 686–689. Bibcode:2023Natur.619..686B. doi:10.1038/d41586-023-02361-7. PMID 37491395. https://ui.adsabs.harvard.edu/abs/2023Natur.619..686B
Carruthers 2004, pp. 270–273 - Carruthers, Peter (2004). The Nature of the Mind: An Introduction (1 ed.). Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-29994-7.
Chen 2023, p. 1141Bringsjord & Govindarajulu 2024, § 8. Philosophy of Artificial IntelligenceButz 2021, pp. 91–92 - Chen, Zhaoman (2023). "Exploration of Youth Social Work Model Driven by Artificial Intelligence". In Hung, Jason C.; Yen, Neil Y.; Chang, Jia-Wei (eds.). Frontier Computing: Theory, Technologies and Applications (FC 2022). Springer. pp. 1138–1146. ISBN 978-981-99-1428-9. https://books.google.com/books?id=C8vAEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA1141
Bringsjord & Govindarajulu 2024, § 8. Philosophy of Artificial IntelligenceFjelland 2020, pp. 1–2 - Bringsjord, Selmer; Govindarajulu, Naveen Sundar (2024). "Artificial Intelligence". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 13 May 2024. Retrieved 6 May 2024. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/artificial-intelligence/
Murphy, Donovan & Smart 2020, pp. 97–99, 103–104, 112 - Murphy, Dominic; Donovan, Caitrin; Smart, Gemma Lucy (2020). "Mental Health and Well-Being in Philosophy". In Sholl, Jonathan; Rattan, Suresh I. S. (eds.). Explaining Health Across the Sciences. Springer. pp. 97–114. ISBN 978-3-030-52663-4. https://books.google.com/books?id=of75DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA103
Gross 2020, pp. 731–735Nairne 2011, pp. 450–453Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 455–457 - Gross, Richard (2020). Psychology: The Science of Mind and Behaviour (8 ed.). Hodder Education. ISBN 978-1-5104-6846-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=Z7TsDwAAQBAJ
Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 466–468Gross 2020, pp. 751–752Nairne 2011, pp. 459–461 - Bernstein, Douglas; Nash, Peggy W. (2006). Essentials of Psychology. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. ISBN 978-0-618-71312-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=4Do-bFrt9tUC
Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 473–474, 476–477Gross 2020, p. 755Nairne 2011, p. 466 - Bernstein, Douglas; Nash, Peggy W. (2006). Essentials of Psychology. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. ISBN 978-0-618-71312-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=4Do-bFrt9tUC
Nairne 2011, p. 471Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 485–486 - Nairne, James S. (2011). Psychology (5 ed.). Cengage Learning. ISBN 978-0-8400-3310-9.
Noll 2009, p. 122Sharma & Branscum 2020, p. 122Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 480–481Nairne 2011, pp. 468–469 - Noll, Richard (2009). The Encyclopedia of Schizophrenia and Other Psychotic Disorders. Infobase Publishing. ISBN 978-0-8160-7508-9. https://books.google.com/books?id=jzoJxps189IC&pg=PA122
Gross 2020, p. 766Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 472–473 - Gross, Richard (2020). Psychology: The Science of Mind and Behaviour (8 ed.). Hodder Education. ISBN 978-1-5104-6846-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=Z7TsDwAAQBAJ
Nairne 2011, pp. 472–473, 475–478Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 457–460Chan 2020, pp. 105–106 - Nairne, James S. (2011). Psychology (5 ed.). Cengage Learning. ISBN 978-0-8400-3310-9.
Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 502–503Nairne 2011, pp. 485–486Gross 2020, pp. 773–774 - Bernstein, Douglas; Nash, Peggy W. (2006). Essentials of Psychology. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. ISBN 978-0-618-71312-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=4Do-bFrt9tUC
Nairne 2011, pp. 493–494Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 503–505Gross 2020, pp. 781–782 - Nairne, James S. (2011). Psychology (5 ed.). Cengage Learning. ISBN 978-0-8400-3310-9.
Nairne 2011, pp. 493, 495–496Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 508–509Gross 2020, pp. 789–790 - Nairne, James S. (2011). Psychology (5 ed.). Cengage Learning. ISBN 978-0-8400-3310-9.
Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 508–509Nairne 2011, pp. 502–503Gross 2020, pp. 784–785 - Bernstein, Douglas; Nash, Peggy W. (2006). Essentials of Psychology. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. ISBN 978-0-618-71312-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=4Do-bFrt9tUC
Nairne 2011, pp. 499–500Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 505–506 - Nairne, James S. (2011). Psychology (5 ed.). Cengage Learning. ISBN 978-0-8400-3310-9.
Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 525–527Nairne 2011, pp. 487–490Gross 2020, pp. 774–779 - Bernstein, Douglas; Nash, Peggy W. (2006). Essentials of Psychology. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. ISBN 978-0-618-71312-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=4Do-bFrt9tUC
Pashler 2013, pp. xxix–xxxFriedenberg, Silverman & Spivey 2022, pp. xix, 12–13 - Pashler, Harold (2013). "Introduction". In Pashler, Harold (ed.). Encyclopedia of the Mind. Sage. pp. xxix–xxxi. ISBN 978-1-4129-5057-2. https://books.google.com/books?id=lu3aMe6kRowC
Friedenberg, Silverman & Spivey 2022, p. 1Uttal 2011, pp. 1–4 - Friedenberg, Jay; Silverman, Gordon; Spivey, Michael (2022). Cognitive Science: An Introduction to the Study of Mind (4 ed.). Sage. ISBN 978-1-5443-8015-5.
Gross 2020, pp. 1–3Friedenberg, Silverman & Spivey 2022, pp. 15–16 - Gross, Richard (2020). Psychology: The Science of Mind and Behaviour (8 ed.). Hodder Education. ISBN 978-1-5104-6846-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=Z7TsDwAAQBAJ
Dawson 2022, pp. 161–162Gross 2020, pp. 4–6 - Dawson, Michael R. W. (2022). What Is Cognitive Psychology?. Athabasca University Press. ISBN 978-1-77199-342-5. https://books.google.com/books?id=QGeEEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA161
Higgs, Cooper & Lee 2019, pp. 3–4Gross 2020, pp. 4–8 - Higgs, Suzanne; Cooper, Alison; Lee, Jonathan (2019). Biological Psychology. Sage. ISBN 978-1-5264-8278-5. https://books.google.com/books?id=rkewDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA3
Gross 2020, pp. 4–6Thornton & Gliga 2020, p. 35Sharma & Sharma 1997, pp. 7–9 - Gross, Richard (2020). Psychology: The Science of Mind and Behaviour (8 ed.). Hodder Education. ISBN 978-1-5104-6846-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=Z7TsDwAAQBAJ
American Psychological Association 2018, § Personality, § Personality Psychology - American Psychological Association (2018). "APA Dictionary of Psychology". American Psychological Association. https://dictionary.apa.org
Gross 2020, pp. 4–8 - Gross, Richard (2020). Psychology: The Science of Mind and Behaviour (8 ed.). Hodder Education. ISBN 978-1-5104-6846-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=Z7TsDwAAQBAJ
Nairne 2011, pp. 11–14Bernstein & Nash 2006, pp. 10–13 - Nairne, James S. (2011). Psychology (5 ed.). Cengage Learning. ISBN 978-0-8400-3310-9.
Psychometrics examines how to measure the mental attributes or psychological constructs underlying the variables. For example, IQ tests are one way to quantify intelligence.[156] /wiki/Psychometrics
Hood 2013, pp. 1314–1315Dumont 2008, pp. 17, 48Howitt & Cramer 2011, pp. 16–17 - Hood, Ralph W. (2013). "Methodology in Psychology". In Runehov, Anne L. C.; Oviedo, Lluis (eds.). Encyclopedia of Sciences and Religions. Springer. pp. 1314–1322. doi:10.1007/978-1-4020-8265-8_695. ISBN 978-1-4020-8265-8. Archived from the original on 13 May 2024. https://link.springer.com/referenceworkentry/10.1007/978-1-4020-8265-8_695
Dumont 2008, pp. 17, 48Howitt & Cramer 2011, pp. 11–12 - Dumont, K. (2008). "2. Research Methods and Statistics". In Nicholas, Lionel (ed.). Introduction to Psychology. University of Capetown Press. pp. 9–48. ISBN 978-1-919895-02-4. https://books.google.com/books?id=MP5X2SK2DCgC&pg=PA48
Howitt & Cramer 2011, pp. 232–233Dumont 2008, pp. 27–28 - Howitt, Dennis; Cramer, Duncan (2011). Introduction to Research Methods in Psychology (3 ed.). Pearson Education. ISBN 978-0-273-73499-4.
Howitt & Cramer 2011, pp. 232–233, 294–295Dumont 2008, pp. 29–30 - Howitt, Dennis; Cramer, Duncan (2011). Introduction to Research Methods in Psychology (3 ed.). Pearson Education. ISBN 978-0-273-73499-4.
Howitt & Cramer 2011, pp. 220–221, 383–384Dumont 2008, p. 28 - Howitt, Dennis; Cramer, Duncan (2011). Introduction to Research Methods in Psychology (3 ed.). Pearson Education. ISBN 978-0-273-73499-4.
Friedenberg, Silverman & Spivey 2022, pp. 17–18Hellier 2014, pp. 31–32Marcus & Jacobson 2012, p. 3 - Friedenberg, Jay; Silverman, Gordon; Spivey, Michael (2022). Cognitive Science: An Introduction to the Study of Mind (4 ed.). Sage. ISBN 978-1-5443-8015-5.
Getz 2023, pp. 1–2, 7–8Cowan, Harter & Kandel 2000, pp. 343–344 - Getz, Glen E. (2023). "History of Neurobiology". Applied Biological Psychology. Springer. pp. 1–12. ISBN 978-0-8261-0922-4. https://connect.springerpub.com/highwire_display/entity_view/node/57243/content_details
Friedenberg, Silverman & Spivey 2022, pp. 17–18Engelmann, Mulckhuyse & Ting 2019, p. 159Scharff 2008, pp. 270–271Hellier 2014, pp. 31–32 - Friedenberg, Jay; Silverman, Gordon; Spivey, Michael (2022). Cognitive Science: An Introduction to the Study of Mind (4 ed.). Sage. ISBN 978-1-5443-8015-5.
Stich & Warfield 2008, pp. ix–xMandik 2014, pp. 1–4, 14Kind 2018, Lead SectionAdams & Beighley 2015, p. 54 - Stich, Stephen P.; Warfield, Ted A. (2008). "Introduction". In Stich, Stephen P.; Warfield, Ted A. (eds.). The Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind. John Wiley & Sons. pp. vii–xi. ISBN 978-0-470-99875-5. https://books.google.com/books?id=NEGK_ZStddkC&pg=PR7
Timpe, § Lead Section, § 3. Free Will and Determinism - Timpe, Kevin. "Free Will". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 6 April 2019. Retrieved 28 March 2024. https://iep.utm.edu/freewill/
Stich & Warfield 2008, pp. ix–xiShaffer 2015, pp. 555–556Audi 2006, § Philosophical Methods - Stich, Stephen P.; Warfield, Ted A. (2008). "Introduction". In Stich, Stephen P.; Warfield, Ted A. (eds.). The Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind. John Wiley & Sons. pp. vii–xi. ISBN 978-0-470-99875-5. https://books.google.com/books?id=NEGK_ZStddkC&pg=PR7
Brown & Fehige 2019, Lead SectionGoffi & Roux 2011, pp. 165, 168–169 - Brown, James Robert; Fehige, Yiftach (2019). "Thought Experiments". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 21 November 2017. Retrieved 29 October 2021. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/thought-experiment/
Smith 2018, Lead Section, § 1. What Is Phenomenology?, §6. Phenomenology and Philosophy of MindSmith 2013, pp. 335–336 - Smith, David Woodruff (2018). "Phenomenology". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 23 June 2020. Retrieved 27 April 2024. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/phenomenology/
Jaworski 2011, pp. 359, 362, 371Flanagan 2005, pp. 603–604Tanney 2022, Lead section - Jaworski, William (2011). Philosophy of Mind: A Comprehensive Introduction (1 ed.). Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-1-4443-3367-1.
Friedenberg, Silverman & Spivey 2022, pp. 2–3Bermúdez 2014, pp. 3, 85Thagard 2023, Lead section, § 3. Representation and Computation - Friedenberg, Jay; Silverman, Gordon; Spivey, Michael (2022). Cognitive Science: An Introduction to the Study of Mind (4 ed.). Sage. ISBN 978-1-5443-8015-5.
Bermúdez 2014, pp. 5–6, 29–30, 59–60Thagard 2023, Lead section, § 1. History - Bermúdez, José Luis (2014). Cognitive Science: An Introduction to the Science of the Mind (2. ed.). Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-107-05162-1.
Friedenberg, Silverman & Spivey 2022, pp. 2–3Bermúdez 2014, pp. 3, 85Thagard 2023, Lead section, § 3. Representation and Computation - Friedenberg, Jay; Silverman, Gordon; Spivey, Michael (2022). Cognitive Science: An Introduction to the Study of Mind (4 ed.). Sage. ISBN 978-1-5443-8015-5.
Friedenberg, Silverman & Spivey 2022, p. 2Spruit 2008, p. 203 - Friedenberg, Jay; Silverman, Gordon; Spivey, Michael (2022). Cognitive Science: An Introduction to the Study of Mind (4 ed.). Sage. ISBN 978-1-5443-8015-5.
Friedenberg, Silverman & Spivey 2022, pp. 8–9Bermúdez 2014, pp. 122–123 - Friedenberg, Jay; Silverman, Gordon; Spivey, Michael (2022). Cognitive Science: An Introduction to the Study of Mind (4 ed.). Sage. ISBN 978-1-5443-8015-5.
Bermúdez 2014, pp. 85, 129–130Koenig 2004, p. 274 - Bermúdez, José Luis (2014). Cognitive Science: An Introduction to the Science of the Mind (2. ed.). Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-107-05162-1.
Avramides 2023, Lead Section, § 1.4 Perceptual Knowledge of Other MindsOvergaard 2010, pp. 255–258 - Avramides, Anita (2023). "Other Minds". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 23 May 2019. Retrieved 7 May 2024. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/other-minds/
American Psychological Association 2018, § Theory of MindDunbar 2007, p. 30Costall & Leuda 2009, p. 41Galandí 2023, p. 437 - American Psychological Association (2018). "APA Dictionary of Psychology". American Psychological Association. https://dictionary.apa.org
Luhrmann 2023, Abstract, § Introduction, § Conceptions of the mind in early ethnographies, § Conclusion: The Understanding of Mind in the West Is PeculiarToren 2010, pp. 577–580, 582Beatty 2019 - Luhrmann, Tanya Marie (2023). Stein, Felix (ed.). "Mind". The Open Encyclopedia of Anthropology. Cambridge University Press. Archived from the original on 7 May 2024. Retrieved 7 May 2024. https://www.anthroencyclopedia.com/entry/mind
Franks 2007, pp. 3055–3056 - Franks, David D. (2007). "Mind". In Ritzer, George (ed.). The Blackwell Encyclopedia of Sociology. Blackwell. pp. 3055–3057. ISBN 978-1-4051-2433-1.
Munroe 2007, § AbstractChandler & Munday 2011 - Munroe, Paul T. (2007). "Intersubjectivity". In Ritzer, George (ed.). The Blackwell Encyclopedia of Sociology (1 ed.). John Wiley & Sons. pp. 1–3. doi:10.1002/9781405165518.wbeosi067.pub2. ISBN 978-1-4051-2433-1. https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1002/9781405165518.wbeosi067.pub2
Karunamuni 2015, pp. 1–2Coseru 2017, Lead Section; § 2.3 The Five AggregatesLaine 1998, Lead Section - Karunamuni, Nandini D. (2015). "The Five-Aggregate Model of the Mind". SAGE Open. 5 (2). doi:10.1177/2158244015583860. https://doi.org/10.1177%2F2158244015583860
Laine 1998, § Philosophy of Mind in the UpaniṣadsRao 2002, pp. 315–316 - Laine, Joy (1998). "Mind, Indian Philosophy of". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-F070-1. ISBN 978-0-415-25069-6. Archived from the original on 8 May 2024. https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/mind-indian-philosophy-of/v-1
Clark, Lints & Smith 2004, pp. 52–53Duncan & LoLordo 2013, p. xvi - Clark, Kelly James; Lints, Richard; Smith, James K. A. (2004). "Mind/Soul/Spirit". 101 Key Terms in Philosophy and Their Importance for Theology. Westminster John Knox Press. ISBN 978-0-664-22524-7. https://books.google.com/books?id=H81iiiPtuGsC&pg=PA52
Rassool 2021, p. 74Rothman 2021, p. 2010 - Rassool, G. Hussein (2021). Islamic Psychology: Human Behaviour and Experience from an Islamic Perspective. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-000-36292-3. https://books.google.com/books?id=_oobEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA74
Wong 2023, Lead SectionHall & Ames 1998 - Wong, David (2023). "Mind (Heart-Mind) in Chinese Philosophy". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 13 May 2024. Retrieved 8 May 2024. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/chinese-mind/
Chazan 2022, pp. 15–16Bartlett & Burton 2007, pp. 81–85Murphy 2003, pp. 5, 19–20Alexander 2013, pp. 109–110 - Chazan, Barry (2022). "What Is "Education"?". Principles and Pedagogies in Jewish Education. Springer. pp. 13–21. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-83925-3_3. ISBN 978-3-030-83925-3. S2CID 239896844. https://doi.org/10.1007%2F978-3-030-83925-3_3
Emaliana 2017, pp. 59–61 - Emaliana, Ive (2017). "Teacher-Centered or Student-Centered Learning Approach To Promote Learning?". Jurnal Sosial Humaniora. 10 (2): 59. doi:10.12962/j24433527.v10i2.2161. S2CID 148796695. https://doi.org/10.12962%2Fj24433527.v10i2.2161
Bartlett & Burton 2007, pp. 81–85Murphy 2003, pp. 5, 19–20Jacobs & Renandya 2019, p. 3 - Bartlett, Steve; Burton, Diana (2007). Introduction to Education Studies (2nd ed.). Sage. ISBN 978-1-4129-2193-0.
Sysling 2022, p. 407Dixon & Shapiro 2022, § 5. Mind, Brain, and MoralityBernstein & Nash 2006, p. 58Bermúdez 2014, pp. 285, 287 - Sysling, Fenneke (2022). "Human Sciences and Technologies of the Self Since the Nineteenth Century". In McCallum, David (ed.). The Palgrave Handbook of the History of Human Sciences. Springer. pp. 401–422. ISBN 978-981-16-7255-2. https://books.google.com/books?id=hIuFEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA407
Stairs 1998, Lead SectionHarperCollins 2022, § ParapsychologyEvans 2004, pp. 584–585 - Stairs, Allen (1998). "Parapsychology". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-W029-1. ISBN 978-0-415-25069-6. Archived from the original on 13 May 2023. https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/parapsychology/v-1