Menu
Home Explore People Places Arts History Plants & Animals Science Life & Culture Technology
On this page
Many-worlds interpretation
Interpretation of quantum mechanics which denies the collapse of the wavefunction

The many-worlds interpretation (MWI) is an interpretation of quantum mechanics proposing that the universal wavefunction is objectively real and that there is no wave function collapse. Instead, all possible outcomes of quantum measurements occur in separate, non-interacting "worlds." Developed by Hugh Everett in 1957 and popularized by Bryce DeWitt, MWI is deterministic and local. Modern versions explain the appearance of collapse through quantum decoherence. As a mainstream interpretation alongside the Copenhagen interpretation and hidden variable theories, MWI addresses the measurement problem and paradoxes like the EPR paradox and Schrödinger's cat by positing a many-branched multiverse.

Related Image Collections Add Image
We don't have any YouTube videos related to Many-worlds interpretation yet.
We don't have any PDF documents related to Many-worlds interpretation yet.
We don't have any Books related to Many-worlds interpretation yet.

Overview of the interpretation

The many-worlds interpretation's key idea is that the linear and unitary dynamics of quantum mechanics applies everywhere and at all times and so describes the whole universe. In particular, it models a measurement as a unitary transformation, a correlation-inducing interaction, between observer and object, without using a collapse postulate, and models observers as ordinary quantum-mechanical systems.21: 35–38  This stands in contrast to the Copenhagen interpretation, in which a measurement is a "primitive" concept, not describable by unitary quantum mechanics; using the Copenhagen interpretation the universe is divided into a quantum and a classical domain, and the collapse postulate is central.22: 29–30  In MWI there is no division between classical and quantum: everything is quantum and there is no collapse. MWI's main conclusion is that the universe (or multiverse in this context) is composed of a quantum superposition of an uncountable23 or undefinable24: 14–17  amount or number of increasingly divergent, non-communicating parallel universes or quantum worlds.25 Sometimes dubbed Everett worlds,26: 234  each is an internally consistent and actualized alternative history or timeline.

The many-worlds interpretation uses decoherence to explain the measurement process and the emergence of a quasi-classical world.2728 Wojciech H. Zurek, one of decoherence theory's pioneers, said: "Under scrutiny of the environment, only pointer states remain unchanged. Other states decohere into mixtures of stable pointer states that can persist, and, in this sense, exist: They are einselected."29 Zurek emphasizes that his work does not depend on a particular interpretation.30

The many-worlds interpretation shares many similarities with the decoherent histories interpretation, which also uses decoherence to explain the process of measurement or wave function collapse.31: 9–11  MWI treats the other histories or worlds as real, since it regards the universal wave function as the "basic physical entity"32: 455  or "the fundamental entity, obeying at all times a deterministic wave equation".33: 115  The decoherent histories interpretation, on the other hand, needs only one of the histories (or worlds) to be real.34: 10 

Several authors, including Everett, John Archibald Wheeler and David Deutsch, call many-worlds a theory or metatheory, rather than just an interpretation.3536: 328  Everett argued that it was the "only completely coherent approach to explaining both the contents of quantum mechanics and the appearance of the world."37 Deutsch dismissed the idea that many-worlds is an "interpretation", saying that to call it an interpretation "is like talking about dinosaurs as an 'interpretation' of fossil records."38: 382 

Formulation

In his 1957 doctoral dissertation, Everett proposed that, rather than relying on external observation for analysis of isolated quantum systems, one could mathematically model an object, as well as its observers, as purely physical systems within the mathematical framework developed by Paul Dirac, John von Neumann, and others, discarding altogether the ad hoc mechanism of wave function collapse.3940

Relative state

Everett's original work introduced the concept of a relative state. Two (or more) subsystems, after a general interaction, become correlated, or as is now said, entangled. Everett noted that such entangled systems can be expressed as the sum of products of states, where the two or more subsystems are each in a state relative to each other. After a measurement or observation one of the pair (or triple...) is the measured, object or observed system, and one other member is the measuring apparatus (which may include an observer) having recorded the state of the measured system. Each product of subsystem states in the overall superposition evolves over time independently of other products. Once the subsystems interact, their states have become correlated or entangled and can no longer be considered independent. In Everett's terminology, each subsystem state was now correlated with its relative state, since each subsystem must now be considered relative to the other subsystems with which it has interacted.

In the example of Schrödinger's cat, after the box is opened, the entangled system is the cat, the poison vial and the observer. One relative triple of states would be the alive cat, the unbroken vial and the observer seeing an alive cat. Another relative triple of states would be the dead cat, the broken vial and the observer seeing a dead cat.

In the example of a measurement of a continuous variable (e.g., position q) the object-observer system decomposes into a continuum of pairs of relative states: the object system's relative state becomes a Dirac delta function each centered on a particular value of q and the corresponding observer relative state representing an observer having recorded the value of q.41: 57–64  The states of the pairs of relative states are, post measurement, correlated with each other.

In Everett's scheme, there is no collapse; instead, the Schrödinger equation, or its quantum field theory, relativistic analog, holds all the time, everywhere. An observation or measurement is modeled by applying the wave equation to the entire system, comprising the object being observed and the observer. One consequence is that every observation causes the combined observer–object's wavefunction to change into a quantum superposition of two or more non-interacting branches.

Thus the process of measurement or observation, or any correlation-inducing interaction, splits the system into sets of relative states, where each set of relative states, forming a branch of the universal wave function, is consistent within itself, and all future measurements (including by multiple observers) will confirm this consistency.

Renamed many-worlds

Everett had referred to the combined observer–object system as split by an observation, each split corresponding to the different or multiple possible outcomes of an observation. These splits generate a branching tree, where each branch is a set of all the states relative to each other. Bryce DeWitt popularized Everett's work with a series of publications calling it the Many Worlds Interpretation. Focusing on the splitting process, DeWitt introduced the term "world" to describe a single branch of that tree, which is a consistent history. All observations or measurements within any branch are consistent within themselves.4243

Since many observation-like events have happened and are constantly happening, Everett's model implies that there are an enormous and growing number of simultaneously existing states or "worlds".44

Properties

MWI removes the observer-dependent role in the quantum measurement process by replacing wave function collapse with the established mechanism of quantum decoherence.45 As the observer's role lies at the heart of all "quantum paradoxes" such as the EPR paradox and von Neumann's "boundary problem", this provides a clearer and easier approach to their resolution.46

Since the Copenhagen interpretation requires the existence of a classical domain beyond the one described by quantum mechanics, it has been criticized as inadequate for the study of cosmology.47 While there is no evidence that Everett was inspired by issues of cosmology,48: 7  he developed his theory with the explicit goal of allowing quantum mechanics to be applied to the universe as a whole, hoping to stimulate the discovery of new phenomena.49 This hope has been realized in the later development of quantum cosmology.50

MWI is a realist, deterministic and local theory. It achieves this by removing wave function collapse, which is indeterministic and nonlocal, from the deterministic and local equations of quantum theory.51

MWI (like other, broader multiverse theories) provides a context for the anthropic principle, which may provide an explanation for the fine-tuned universe.5253

MWI depends crucially on the linearity of quantum mechanics, which underpins the superposition principle. If the final theory of everything is non-linear with respect to wavefunctions, then many-worlds is invalid.5455565758 All quantum field theories are linear and compatible with the MWI, a point Everett emphasized as a motivation for the MWI.59 While quantum gravity or string theory may be non-linear in this respect,60 there is as yet no evidence of this.6162

Weingarten63 and Taylor & McCulloch64 have made separate proposals for how to define wavefunction branches in terms of quantum circuit complexity.

Alternative to wavefunction collapse

As with the other interpretations of quantum mechanics, the many-worlds interpretation is motivated by behavior that can be illustrated by the double-slit experiment. When particles of light (or anything else) pass through the double slit, a calculation assuming wavelike behavior of light can be used to identify where the particles are likely to be observed. Yet when the particles are observed in this experiment, they appear as particles (i.e., at definite places) and not as non-localized waves.

Some versions of the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics proposed a process of "collapse" in which an indeterminate quantum system would probabilistically collapse onto, or select, just one determinate outcome to "explain" this phenomenon of observation. Wave function collapse was widely regarded as artificial and ad hoc,65 so an alternative interpretation in which the behavior of measurement could be understood from more fundamental physical principles was considered desirable.

Everett's PhD work provided such an interpretation. He argued that for a composite system—such as a subject (the "observer" or measuring apparatus) observing an object (the "observed" system, such as a particle)—the claim that either the observer or the observed has a well-defined state is meaningless; in modern parlance, the observer and the observed have become entangled: we can only specify the state of one relative to the other, i.e., the state of the observer and the observed are correlated after the observation is made. This led Everett to derive from the unitary, deterministic dynamics alone (i.e., without assuming wave function collapse) the notion of a relativity of states.

Everett noticed that the unitary, deterministic dynamics alone entailed that after an observation is made each element of the quantum superposition of the combined subject–object wave function contains two "relative states": a "collapsed" object state and an associated observer who has observed the same collapsed outcome; what the observer sees and the state of the object have become correlated by the act of measurement or observation. The subsequent evolution of each pair of relative subject–object states proceeds with complete indifference as to the presence or absence of the other elements, as if wave function collapse has occurred,66: 67, 78  which has the consequence that later observations are always consistent with the earlier observations. Thus the appearance of the object's wave function's collapse has emerged from the unitary, deterministic theory itself. (This answered Einstein's early criticism of quantum theory: that the theory should define what is observed, not for the observables to define the theory.)67 Since the wave function appears to have collapsed then, Everett reasoned, there was no need to actually assume that it had collapsed. And so, invoking Occam's razor, he removed the postulate of wave function collapse from the theory.68: 8 

Testability

In 1985, David Deutsch proposed a variant of the Wigner's friend thought experiment as a test of many-worlds versus the Copenhagen interpretation.69 It consists of an experimenter (Wigner's friend) making a measurement on a quantum system in an isolated laboratory, and another experimenter (Wigner) who would make a measurement on the first one. According to the many-worlds theory, the first experimenter would end up in a macroscopic superposition of seeing one result of the measurement in one branch, and another result in another branch. The second experimenter could then interfere these two branches in order to test whether it is in fact in a macroscopic superposition or has collapsed into a single branch, as predicted by the Copenhagen interpretation. Since then Lockwood, Vaidman, and others have made similar proposals,70 which require placing macroscopic objects in a coherent superposition and interfering them, a task currently beyond experimental capability.

Probability and the Born rule

Since the many-worlds interpretation's inception, physicists have been puzzled about the role of probability in it. As put by Wallace, there are two facets to the question:71 the incoherence problem, which asks why we should assign probabilities at all to outcomes that are certain to occur in some worlds, and the quantitative problem, which asks why the probabilities should be given by the Born rule.

Everett tried to answer these questions in the paper that introduced many-worlds. To address the incoherence problem, he argued that an observer who makes a sequence of measurements on a quantum system will in general have an apparently random sequence of results in their memory, which justifies the use of probabilities to describe the measurement process.72: 69–70  To address the quantitative problem, Everett proposed a derivation of the Born rule based on the properties that a measure on the branches of the wave function should have.73: 70–72  His derivation has been criticized as relying on unmotivated assumptions.74 Since then several other derivations of the Born rule in the many-worlds framework have been proposed. There is no consensus on whether this has been successful.757677

Frequentism

DeWitt and Graham78 and Farhi et al.,79 among others, have proposed derivations of the Born rule based on a frequentist interpretation of probability. They try to show that in the limit of uncountably many measurements, no worlds would have relative frequencies that didn't match the probabilities given by the Born rule, but these derivations have been shown to be mathematically incorrect.8081

Decision theory

A decision-theoretic derivation of the Born rule was produced by David Deutsch (1999)82 and refined by Wallace83848586 and Saunders.8788 They consider an agent who takes part in a quantum gamble: the agent makes a measurement on a quantum system, branches as a consequence, and each of the agent's future selves receives a reward that depends on the measurement result. The agent uses decision theory to evaluate the price they would pay to take part in such a gamble, and concludes that the price is given by the utility of the rewards weighted according to the Born rule. Some reviews have been positive, although these arguments remain highly controversial; some theoretical physicists have taken them as supporting the case for parallel universes.89 For example, a New Scientist story on a 2007 conference about Everettian interpretations90 quoted physicist Andy Albrecht as saying, "This work will go down as one of the most important developments in the history of science."91 In contrast, the philosopher Huw Price, also attending the conference, found the Deutsch–Wallace–Saunders approach fundamentally flawed.92

Symmetries and invariance

In 2005, Zurek93 produced a derivation of the Born rule based on the symmetries of entangled states; Schlosshauer and Fine argue that Zurek's derivation is not rigorous, as it does not define what probability is and has several unstated assumptions about how it should behave.94

In 2016, Charles Sebens and Sean M. Carroll, building on work by Lev Vaidman,95 proposed a similar approach based on self-locating uncertainty.96 In this approach, decoherence creates multiple identical copies of observers, who can assign credences to being on different branches using the Born rule. The Sebens–Carroll approach has been criticized by Adrian Kent,97 and Vaidman does not find it satisfactory.98

Branch counting

In 2021, Simon Saunders produced a branch counting derivation of the Born rule. The crucial feature of this approach is to define the branches so that they all have the same magnitude or 2-norm. The ratios of the numbers of branches thus defined give the probabilities of the various outcomes of a measurement, in accordance with the Born rule.99

The preferred basis problem

As originally formulated by Everett and DeWitt, the many-worlds interpretation had a privileged role for measurements: they determined which basis of a quantum system would give rise to the eponymous worlds. Without this the theory was ambiguous, as a quantum state can equally well be described (e.g.) as having a well-defined position or as being a superposition of two delocalized states. The assumption is that the preferred basis to use is the one which assigns a unique measurement outcome to each world. This special role for measurements is problematic for the theory, as it contradicts Everett and DeWitt's goal of having a reductionist theory and undermines their criticism of the ill-defined measurement postulate of the Copenhagen interpretation.100101 This is known today as the preferred basis problem.

The preferred basis problem has been solved, according to Saunders and Wallace, among others,102 by incorporating decoherence into the many-worlds theory.103104105106 In this approach, the preferred basis does not have to be postulated, but rather is identified as the basis stable under environmental decoherence. In this way measurements no longer play a special role; rather, any interaction that causes decoherence causes the world to split. Since decoherence is never complete, there will always remain some infinitesimal overlap between two worlds, making it arbitrary whether a pair of worlds has split or not.107 Wallace argues that this is not problematic: it only shows that worlds are not a part of the fundamental ontology, but rather of the emergent ontology, where these approximate, effective descriptions are routine in the physical sciences.108109 Since in this approach the worlds are derived, it follows that they must be present in any other interpretation of quantum mechanics that does not have a collapse mechanism, such as Bohmian mechanics.110

This approach to deriving the preferred basis has been criticized as creating circularity with derivations of probability in the many-worlds interpretation, as decoherence theory depends on probability and probability depends on the ontology derived from decoherence.111112113 Wallace contends that decoherence theory depends not on probability but only on the notion that one is allowed to do approximations in physics.114: 253–254 

History

MWI originated in Everett's Princeton University PhD thesis "The Theory of the Universal Wave Function",115 developed under his thesis advisor John Archibald Wheeler, a shorter summary of which was published in 1957 under the title "Relative State Formulation of Quantum Mechanics" (Wheeler contributed the title "relative state";116 Everett originally called his approach the "Correlation Interpretation", where "correlation" refers to quantum entanglement). The phrase "many-worlds" is due to Bryce DeWitt,117 who was responsible for the wider popularization of Everett's theory, which had been largely ignored for a decade after publication in 1957.118

Everett's proposal was not without precedent. In 1952, Erwin Schrödinger gave a lecture in Dublin in which at one point he jocularly warned his audience that what he was about to say might "seem lunatic". He went on to assert that while the Schrödinger equation seemed to be describing several different histories, they were "not alternatives but all really happen simultaneously". According to David Deutsch, this is the earliest known reference to many-worlds; Jeffrey A. Barrett describes it as indicating the similarity of "general views" between Everett and Schrödinger.119120121 Schrödinger's writings from the period also contain elements resembling the modal interpretation originated by Bas van Fraassen. Because Schrödinger subscribed to a kind of post-Machian neutral monism, in which "matter" and "mind" are only different aspects or arrangements of the same common elements, treating the wave function as physical and treating it as information became interchangeable.122

Leon Cooper and Deborah Van Vechten developed a very similar approach before reading Everett's work.123 Zeh also came to the same conclusions as Everett before reading his work, then built a new theory of quantum decoherence based on these ideas.124

According to people who knew him, Everett believed in the literal reality of the other quantum worlds.125 His son and wife reported that he "never wavered in his belief over his many-worlds theory".126 In their detailed review of Everett's work, Osnaghi, Freitas, and Freire Jr. note that Everett consistently used quotes around "real" to indicate a meaning within scientific practice.127: 107 

Reception

MWI's initial reception was overwhelmingly negative, in the sense that it was ignored, with the notable exception of DeWitt. Wheeler made considerable efforts to formulate the theory in a way that would be palatable to Bohr, visited Copenhagen in 1956 to discuss it with him, and convinced Everett to visit as well, which happened in 1959. Nevertheless, Bohr and his collaborators completely rejected the theory.128 Everett had already left academia in 1957, never to return, and in 1980, Wheeler disavowed the theory.129

Support

One of MWI's strongest longtime advocates is David Deutsch.130 According to him, the single photon interference pattern observed in the double slit experiment can be explained by interference of photons in multiple universes. Viewed this way, the single photon interference experiment is indistinguishable from the multiple photon interference experiment. In a more practical vein, in one of the earliest papers on quantum computing,131 Deutsch suggested that parallelism that results from MWI could lead to "a method by which certain probabilistic tasks can be performed faster by a universal quantum computer than by any classical restriction of it". He also proposed that MWI will be testable (at least against "naive" Copenhagenism) when reversible computers become conscious via the reversible observation of spin.132

Equivocal

Philosophers of science James Ladyman and Don Ross say that MWI could be true, but do not embrace it. They note that no quantum theory is yet empirically adequate for describing all of reality, given its lack of unification with general relativity, and so do not see a reason to regard any interpretation of quantum mechanics as the final word in metaphysics. They also suggest that the multiple branches may be an artifact of incomplete descriptions and of using quantum mechanics to represent the states of macroscopic objects. They argue that macroscopic objects are significantly different from microscopic objects in not being isolated from the environment, and that using quantum formalism to describe them lacks explanatory and descriptive power and accuracy.133

Rejection

Some scientists consider some aspects of MWI to be unfalsifiable and hence unscientific because the multiple parallel universes are non-communicating, in the sense that no information can be passed between them.134135

Victor J. Stenger remarked that Murray Gell-Mann's published work explicitly rejects the existence of simultaneous parallel universes.136 Collaborating with James Hartle, Gell-Mann worked toward the development of a more "palatable" post-Everett quantum mechanics. Stenger thought it fair to say that most physicists find MWI too extreme, though it "has merit in finding a place for the observer inside the system being analyzed and doing away with the troublesome notion of wave function collapse".137

Roger Penrose argues that the idea is flawed because it is based on an oversimplified version of quantum mechanics that does not account for gravity. In his view, applying conventional quantum mechanics to the universe implies the MWI, but the lack of a successful theory of quantum gravity negates the claimed universality of conventional quantum mechanics.138 According to Penrose, "the rules must change when gravity is involved". He further asserts that gravity helps anchor reality and "blurry" events have only one allowable outcome: "electrons, atoms, molecules, etc., are so minute that they require almost no amount of energy to maintain their gravity, and therefore their overlapping states. They can stay in that state forever, as described in standard quantum theory". On the other hand, "in the case of large objects, the duplicate states disappear in an instant due to the fact that these objects create a large gravitational field".139140

Philosopher of science Robert P. Crease says that MWI is "one of the most implausible and unrealistic ideas in the history of science" because it means that everything conceivable happens.141 Science writer Philip Ball calls MWI's implications fantasies, since "beneath their apparel of scientific equations or symbolic logic, they are acts of imagination, of 'just supposing'".142

Theoretical physicist Gerard 't Hooft also dismisses the idea: "I do not believe that we have to live with the many-worlds interpretation. Indeed, it would be a stupendous number of parallel worlds, which are only there because physicists couldn't decide which of them is real."143

Asher Peres was an outspoken critic of MWI. A section of his 1993 textbook had the title Everett's interpretation and other bizarre theories. Peres argued that the various many-worlds interpretations merely shift the arbitrariness or vagueness of the collapse postulate to the question of when "worlds" can be regarded as separate, and that no objective criterion for that separation can actually be formulated.144

Polls

A poll of 72 "leading quantum cosmologists and other quantum field theorists" conducted before 1991 by L. David Raub showed 58% agreement with "Yes, I think MWI is true".145

Max Tegmark reports the result of a "highly unscientific" poll taken at a 1997 quantum mechanics workshop. According to Tegmark, "The many worlds interpretation (MWI) scored second, comfortably ahead of the consistent histories and Bohm interpretations."146

In response to Sean M. Carroll's statement "As crazy as it sounds, most working physicists buy into the many-worlds theory",147 Michael Nielsen counters: "at a quantum computing conference at Cambridge in 1998, a many-worlder surveyed the audience of approximately 200 people... Many-worlds did just fine, garnering support on a level comparable to, but somewhat below, Copenhagen and decoherence." But Nielsen notes that it seemed most attendees found it to be a waste of time: Peres "got a huge and sustained round of applause…when he got up at the end of the polling and asked 'And who here believes the laws of physics are decided by a democratic vote?'"148

A 2005 poll of fewer than 40 students and researchers taken after a course on the Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics at the Institute for Quantum Computing University of Waterloo found "Many Worlds (and decoherence)" to be the least favored.149

A 2011 poll of 33 participants at an Austrian conference on quantum foundations found 6 endorsed MWI, 8 "Information-based/information-theoretical", and 14 Copenhagen;150 the authors remark that MWI received a similar percentage of votes as in Tegmark's 1997 poll.151

Speculative implications

See also: Parallel universes in fiction

DeWitt has said that Everett, Wheeler, and Graham "do not in the end exclude any element of the superposition. All the worlds are there, even those in which everything goes wrong and all the statistical laws break down."152 Tegmark affirmed that absurd or highly unlikely events are rare but inevitable under MWI: "Things inconsistent with the laws of physics will never happen—everything else will... it's important to keep track of the statistics, since even if everything conceivable happens somewhere, really freak events happen only exponentially rarely."153 David Deutsch speculates in his book The Beginning of Infinity that some fiction, such as alternate history, could occur somewhere in the multiverse, as long as it is consistent with the laws of physics.154155

According to Ladyman and Ross, many seemingly physically plausible but unrealized possibilities, such as those discussed in other scientific fields, generally have no counterparts in other branches, because they are in fact incompatible with the universal wave function.156 According to Carroll, human decision-making, contrary to common misconceptions, is best thought of as a classical process, not a quantum one, because it works on the level of neurochemistry rather than fundamental particles. Human decisions do not cause the world to branch into equally realized outcomes; even for subjectively difficult decisions, the "weight" of realized outcomes is almost entirely concentrated in a single branch.157: 214–216 

Quantum suicide is a thought experiment in quantum mechanics and the philosophy of physics that can purportedly distinguish between the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics and the many-worlds interpretation by a variation of the Schrödinger's cat thought experiment, from the cat's point of view. Quantum immortality refers to the subjective experience of surviving quantum suicide.158 Most experts believe the experiment would not work in the real world, because the world with the surviving experimenter has a lower "measure" than the world before the experiment, making it less likely that the experimenter will experience their survival.159: 371 160161162

See also

Notes

Further reading

References

  1. Everett, Hugh; Wheeler, J. A.; DeWitt, B. S.; Cooper, L. N.; Van Vechten, D.; Graham, N. (1973). DeWitt, Bryce; Graham, R. Neill (eds.). The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton Series in Physics. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. p. v. ISBN 0-691-08131-X. 0-691-08131-X

  2. Tegmark, Max (1998). "The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics: Many Worlds or Many Words?". Fortschritte der Physik. 46 (6–8): 855–862. arXiv:quant-ph/9709032. Bibcode:1998ForPh..46..855T. doi:10.1002/(SICI)1521-3978(199811)46:6/8<855::AID-PROP855>3.0.CO;2-Q. S2CID 212466. /wiki/ArXiv_(identifier)

  3. Everett, Hugh; Wheeler, J. A.; DeWitt, B. S.; Cooper, L. N.; Van Vechten, D.; Graham, N. (1973). DeWitt, Bryce; Graham, R. Neill (eds.). The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton Series in Physics. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. p. v. ISBN 0-691-08131-X. 0-691-08131-X

  4. Brown, Harvey R.; Christopher G. Timpson (2016). "Bell on Bell's Theorem: The Changing Face of Nonlocality". In Mary Bell; Shan Gao (eds.). Quantum Nonlocality and Reality: 50 years of Bell's theorem. Cambridge University Press. pp. 91–123. arXiv:1501.03521. doi:10.1017/CBO9781316219393.008. ISBN 9781316219393. S2CID 118686956. On locality:"Amongst those who have taken Everett's approach to quantum theory at all seriously as an option, it is a commonplace that—given an Everettian interpretation—quantum theory is (dynamically) local-there is no action-at-a-distance" on determinism:"But zooming-out (in a God's-eye view) from a particular branch will be seen all the other branches, each with a different result of measurement being recorded and observed, all coexisting equally; and all underpinned by (supervenient on) the deterministically, unitarily, evolving universal wavefunction" 9781316219393

  5. Hugh Everett Theory of the Universal Wavefunction, Thesis, Princeton University, (1956, 1973), pp. 1–140. /wiki/Hugh_Everett

  6. Everett, Hugh (1957). "Relative State Formulation of Quantum Mechanics". Reviews of Modern Physics. 29 (3): 454–462. Bibcode:1957RvMP...29..454E. doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.29.454. Archived from the original on 2011-10-27. Retrieved 2011-10-24. /wiki/Hugh_Everett

  7. DeWitt, Bryce S. (1970). "Quantum mechanics and reality". Physics Today. 23 (9): 30–35. Bibcode:1970PhT....23i..30D. doi:10.1063/1.3022331. See also Ballentine, Leslie E.; Pearle, Philip; Walker, Evan Harris; Sachs, Mendel; Koga, Toyoki; Gerver, Joseph; DeWitt, Bryce (1971). "Quantum-mechanics debate". Physics Today. 24 (4): 36–44. Bibcode:1971PhT....24d..36.. doi:10.1063/1.3022676. https://doi.org/10.1063%2F1.3022331

  8. Everett, Hugh; Wheeler, J. A.; DeWitt, B. S.; Cooper, L. N.; Van Vechten, D.; Graham, N. (1973). DeWitt, Bryce; Graham, R. Neill (eds.). The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton Series in Physics. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. p. v. ISBN 0-691-08131-X. 0-691-08131-X

  9. Cecile M. DeWitt, John A. Wheeler (eds,) The Everett–Wheeler Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics, Battelle Rencontres: 1967 Lectures in Mathematics and Physics (1968). /wiki/C%C3%A9cile_DeWitt-Morette

  10. Bryce Seligman DeWitt, The Many-Universes Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics, Proceedings of the International School of Physics "Enrico Fermi" Course IL: Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, Academic Press (1972). /wiki/Bryce_Seligman_DeWitt

  11. Tegmark, Max (1998). "The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics: Many Worlds or Many Words?". Fortschritte der Physik. 46 (6–8): 855–862. arXiv:quant-ph/9709032. Bibcode:1998ForPh..46..855T. doi:10.1002/(SICI)1521-3978(199811)46:6/8<855::AID-PROP855>3.0.CO;2-Q. S2CID 212466. /wiki/ArXiv_(identifier)

  12. H. Dieter Zeh, On the Interpretation of Measurement in Quantum Theory, Foundations of Physics, vol. 1, pp. 69–76, (1970). /wiki/H._Dieter_Zeh

  13. Wojciech Hubert Zurek, Decoherence and the transition from quantum to classical, Physics Today, vol. 44, issue 10, pp. 36–44, (1991). /wiki/Wojciech_Hubert_Zurek

  14. Wojciech Hubert Zurek, Decoherence, einselection, and the quantum origins of the classical, Reviews of Modern Physics, 75, pp. 715–775, (2003). /wiki/Wojciech_Hubert_Zurek

  15. Schlosshauer, Maximilian; Kofler, Johannes; Zeilinger, Anton (August 2013). "A snapshot of foundational attitudes toward quantum mechanics". Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 44 (3): 222–230. arXiv:1301.1069. Bibcode:2013SHPMP..44..222S. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2013.04.004. https://doi.org/10.1016%2Fj.shpsb.2013.04.004

  16. Tegmark, Max (1998). "The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics: Many Worlds or Many Words?". Fortschritte der Physik. 46 (6–8): 855–862. arXiv:quant-ph/9709032. Bibcode:1998ForPh..46..855T. doi:10.1002/(SICI)1521-3978(199811)46:6/8<855::AID-PROP855>3.0.CO;2-Q. S2CID 212466. /wiki/ArXiv_(identifier)

  17. Hugh Everett Theory of the Universal Wavefunction, Thesis, Princeton University, (1956, 1973), pp. 1–140. /wiki/Hugh_Everett

  18. Everett, Hugh (1957). "Relative State Formulation of Quantum Mechanics". Reviews of Modern Physics. 29 (3): 454–462. Bibcode:1957RvMP...29..454E. doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.29.454. Archived from the original on 2011-10-27. Retrieved 2011-10-24. /wiki/Hugh_Everett

  19. Everett, Hugh; Wheeler, J. A.; DeWitt, B. S.; Cooper, L. N.; Van Vechten, D.; Graham, N. (1973). DeWitt, Bryce; Graham, R. Neill (eds.). The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton Series in Physics. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. p. v. ISBN 0-691-08131-X. 0-691-08131-X

  20. DeWitt, Bryce S. (1970). "Quantum mechanics and reality". Physics Today. 23 (9): 30–35. Bibcode:1970PhT....23i..30D. doi:10.1063/1.3022331. See also Ballentine, Leslie E.; Pearle, Philip; Walker, Evan Harris; Sachs, Mendel; Koga, Toyoki; Gerver, Joseph; DeWitt, Bryce (1971). "Quantum-mechanics debate". Physics Today. 24 (4): 36–44. Bibcode:1971PhT....24d..36.. doi:10.1063/1.3022676. https://doi.org/10.1063%2F1.3022331

  21. Wallace, David (2012). The Emergent Multiverse: Quantum Theory According to the Everett Interpretation. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-954696-1. 978-0-19-954696-1

  22. Wallace, David (2012). The Emergent Multiverse: Quantum Theory According to the Everett Interpretation. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-954696-1. 978-0-19-954696-1

  23. Osnaghi, Stefano; Freitas, Fabio; Olival Freire, Jr (2009). "The Origin of the Everettian Heresy". Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 40 (2): 97–123. Bibcode:2009SHPMP..40...97O. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.397.3933. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2008.10.002. /wiki/Olival_Freire,_Jr.

  24. Wallace, David (2010). "Decoherence and Ontology, or: How I Learned To Stop Worrying And Love FAPP". In Saunders, S.; Barrett, J.; Kent, A.; Wallace, D. (eds.). Many Worlds? Everett, Quantum Theory and Reality. Oxford University Press. arXiv:1111.2189. /wiki/ArXiv_(identifier)

  25. Everett, Hugh; Wheeler, J. A.; DeWitt, B. S.; Cooper, L. N.; Van Vechten, D.; Graham, N. (1973). DeWitt, Bryce; Graham, R. Neill (eds.). The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton Series in Physics. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. p. v. ISBN 0-691-08131-X. 0-691-08131-X

  26. Everett, Hugh; Wheeler, J. A.; DeWitt, B. S.; Cooper, L. N.; Van Vechten, D.; Graham, N. (1973). DeWitt, Bryce; Graham, R. Neill (eds.). The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton Series in Physics. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. p. v. ISBN 0-691-08131-X. 0-691-08131-X

  27. Wallace, David (2010). "Decoherence and Ontology, or: How I Learned To Stop Worrying And Love FAPP". In Saunders, S.; Barrett, J.; Kent, A.; Wallace, D. (eds.). Many Worlds? Everett, Quantum Theory and Reality. Oxford University Press. arXiv:1111.2189. /wiki/ArXiv_(identifier)

  28. Saunders, Simon (2010). "Many Worlds? An Introduction". In Saunders, S.; Barrett, J.; Kent, A.; Wallace, D. (eds.). Many Worlds? Everett, Quantum Theory and Reality (PDF). Oxford University Press. /wiki/Simon_Saunders

  29. Zurek, Wojciech (March 2009). "Quantum Darwinism". Nature Physics. 5 (3): 181–188. arXiv:0903.5082. Bibcode:2009NatPh...5..181Z. doi:10.1038/nphys1202. S2CID 119205282. /wiki/Wojciech_Hubert_Zurek

  30. "Relative states of Everett come to mind. One could speculate about reality of branches with other outcomes. We abstain from this; our discussion is interpretation-free, and this is a virtue."[17]

  31. Saunders, Simon (2010). "Many Worlds? An Introduction". In Saunders, S.; Barrett, J.; Kent, A.; Wallace, D. (eds.). Many Worlds? Everett, Quantum Theory and Reality (PDF). Oxford University Press. /wiki/Simon_Saunders

  32. Everett, Hugh (1957). "Relative State Formulation of Quantum Mechanics". Reviews of Modern Physics. 29 (3): 454–462. Bibcode:1957RvMP...29..454E. doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.29.454. Archived from the original on 2011-10-27. Retrieved 2011-10-24. /wiki/Hugh_Everett

  33. Hugh Everett Theory of the Universal Wavefunction, Thesis, Princeton University, (1956, 1973), pp. 1–140. /wiki/Hugh_Everett

  34. Saunders, Simon (2010). "Many Worlds? An Introduction". In Saunders, S.; Barrett, J.; Kent, A.; Wallace, D. (eds.). Many Worlds? Everett, Quantum Theory and Reality (PDF). Oxford University Press. /wiki/Simon_Saunders

  35. Osnaghi, Stefano; Freitas, Fabio; Olival Freire, Jr (2009). "The Origin of the Everettian Heresy". Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 40 (2): 97–123. Bibcode:2009SHPMP..40...97O. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.397.3933. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2008.10.002. /wiki/Olival_Freire,_Jr.

  36. Skyrms, Brian (1976). "Possible Worlds, Physics and Metaphysics". Philosophical Studies. 30 (5): 323–332. doi:10.1007/BF00357930. S2CID 170852547. /wiki/Brian_Skyrms

  37. Everett, Hugh (1980-04-07), Hugh Everett letter to David Raub, 7-April-1980, retrieved 2023-08-26 https://calisphere.org/item/ark:/81235/d83t9dk9g/

  38. Byrne, Peter (2010). The Many Worlds of Hugh Everett III: Multiple Universes, Mutual Assured Destruction, and the Meltdown of a Nuclear Family. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-955227-6. 978-0-19-955227-6

  39. Hugh Everett Theory of the Universal Wavefunction, Thesis, Princeton University, (1956, 1973), pp. 1–140. /wiki/Hugh_Everett

  40. Everett, Hugh; Wheeler, J. A.; DeWitt, B. S.; Cooper, L. N.; Van Vechten, D.; Graham, N. (1973). DeWitt, Bryce; Graham, R. Neill (eds.). The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton Series in Physics. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. p. v. ISBN 0-691-08131-X. 0-691-08131-X

  41. Hugh Everett Theory of the Universal Wavefunction, Thesis, Princeton University, (1956, 1973), pp. 1–140. /wiki/Hugh_Everett

  42. Hugh Everett Theory of the Universal Wavefunction, Thesis, Princeton University, (1956, 1973), pp. 1–140. /wiki/Hugh_Everett

  43. Everett, Hugh; Wheeler, J. A.; DeWitt, B. S.; Cooper, L. N.; Van Vechten, D.; Graham, N. (1973). DeWitt, Bryce; Graham, R. Neill (eds.). The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton Series in Physics. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. p. v. ISBN 0-691-08131-X. 0-691-08131-X

  44. "every quantum transition taking place on every star, in every galaxy, in every remote corner of the universe is splitting our local world on earth into myriads of copies of itself."[6] DeWitt later softened this extreme view, viewing splitting as decoherence driven and local, in line with other modern commentators.[21]

  45. Schlosshauer, Max (2019-10-25). "Quantum decoherence". Physics Reports. 831: 1–57. arXiv:1911.06282. Bibcode:2019PhR...831....1S. doi:10.1016/j.physrep.2019.10.001. S2CID 208006050. /wiki/ArXiv_(identifier)

  46. Everett, Hugh (1957). "Relative State Formulation of Quantum Mechanics". Reviews of Modern Physics. 29 (3): 454–462. Bibcode:1957RvMP...29..454E. doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.29.454. Archived from the original on 2011-10-27. Retrieved 2011-10-24. /wiki/Hugh_Everett

  47. Gell-Mann, M.; Hartle, J. B. (1990). "Quantum mechanics in the light of quantum cosmology". In Zurek, W. H. (ed.). Complexity, Entropy, and the Physics of Information. Addison-Wesley. arXiv:1803.04605. /wiki/ArXiv_(identifier)

  48. Osnaghi, Stefano; Freitas, Fabio; Olival Freire, Jr (2009). "The Origin of the Everettian Heresy". Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 40 (2): 97–123. Bibcode:2009SHPMP..40...97O. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.397.3933. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2008.10.002. /wiki/Olival_Freire,_Jr.

  49. Everett, Hugh (1957). "Relative State Formulation of Quantum Mechanics". Reviews of Modern Physics. 29 (3): 454–462. Bibcode:1957RvMP...29..454E. doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.29.454. Archived from the original on 2011-10-27. Retrieved 2011-10-24. /wiki/Hugh_Everett

  50. Gell-Mann, Murray; Hartle, James B. (January 1997). Quantum Mechanics in the Light of Quantum Cosmology. Vol. 4. World Scientific. pp. 347–369. doi:10.1142/9789812819895_0036. ISBN 978-981-02-2844-6. 978-981-02-2844-6

  51. Brown, Harvey R.; Christopher G. Timpson (2016). "Bell on Bell's Theorem: The Changing Face of Nonlocality". In Mary Bell; Shan Gao (eds.). Quantum Nonlocality and Reality: 50 years of Bell's theorem. Cambridge University Press. pp. 91–123. arXiv:1501.03521. doi:10.1017/CBO9781316219393.008. ISBN 9781316219393. S2CID 118686956. On locality:"Amongst those who have taken Everett's approach to quantum theory at all seriously as an option, it is a commonplace that—given an Everettian interpretation—quantum theory is (dynamically) local-there is no action-at-a-distance" on determinism:"But zooming-out (in a God's-eye view) from a particular branch will be seen all the other branches, each with a different result of measurement being recorded and observed, all coexisting equally; and all underpinned by (supervenient on) the deterministically, unitarily, evolving universal wavefunction" 9781316219393

  52. Paul C. W. Davies, Other Worlds, chapters 8 & 9 The Anthropic Principle & Is the Universe an accident?, (1980) ISBN 0-460-04400-1. /wiki/Paul_C.W._Davies

  53. Paul C. W. Davies, The Accidental Universe, (1982) ISBN 0-521-28692-1. /wiki/Paul_C.W._Davies

  54. DeWitt, Bryce S. (1970). "Quantum mechanics and reality". Physics Today. 23 (9): 30–35. Bibcode:1970PhT....23i..30D. doi:10.1063/1.3022331. See also Ballentine, Leslie E.; Pearle, Philip; Walker, Evan Harris; Sachs, Mendel; Koga, Toyoki; Gerver, Joseph; DeWitt, Bryce (1971). "Quantum-mechanics debate". Physics Today. 24 (4): 36–44. Bibcode:1971PhT....24d..36.. doi:10.1063/1.3022676. https://doi.org/10.1063%2F1.3022331

  55. Everett, Hugh; Wheeler, J. A.; DeWitt, B. S.; Cooper, L. N.; Van Vechten, D.; Graham, N. (1973). DeWitt, Bryce; Graham, R. Neill (eds.). The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton Series in Physics. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. p. v. ISBN 0-691-08131-X. 0-691-08131-X

  56. Everett, Hugh (1957). "Relative State Formulation of Quantum Mechanics". Reviews of Modern Physics. 29 (3): 454–462. Bibcode:1957RvMP...29..454E. doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.29.454. Archived from the original on 2011-10-27. Retrieved 2011-10-24. /wiki/Hugh_Everett

  57. Cecile M. DeWitt, John A. Wheeler (eds,) The Everett–Wheeler Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics, Battelle Rencontres: 1967 Lectures in Mathematics and Physics (1968). /wiki/C%C3%A9cile_DeWitt-Morette

  58. Bryce Seligman DeWitt, The Many-Universes Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics, Proceedings of the International School of Physics "Enrico Fermi" Course IL: Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, Academic Press (1972). /wiki/Bryce_Seligman_DeWitt

  59. Everett, Hugh (1957). "Relative State Formulation of Quantum Mechanics". Reviews of Modern Physics. 29 (3): 454–462. Bibcode:1957RvMP...29..454E. doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.29.454. Archived from the original on 2011-10-27. Retrieved 2011-10-24. /wiki/Hugh_Everett

  60. Penrose, Roger (August 1991). "Roger Penrose Looks Beyond the Classic-Quantum Dichotomy". Sciencewatch. Archived from the original on 2007-10-23. Retrieved 2007-10-21. /wiki/Roger_Penrose

  61. Steven Weinberg, Dreams of a Final Theory: The Search for the Fundamental Laws of Nature (1993), ISBN 0-09-922391-0, pp. 68–69. /wiki/Steven_Weinberg

  62. Steven Weinberg. Testing Quantum Mechanics, Annals of Physics Vol. 194, #2 (1989), pp. 336–386. /wiki/Steven_Weinberg

  63. Weingarten, Don (5 April 2022). "Macroscopic Reality from Quantum Complexity". Foundations of Physics. 52 (2): 45. arXiv:2105.04545. doi:10.1007/s10701-022-00554-0. ISSN 1572-9516. https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s10701-022-00554-0

  64. Taylor, Jordan; McCulloch, Ian (25 March 2025). "Wavefunction branching: when you can't tell pure states from mixed states". Quantum. 9: 1670. arXiv:2308.04494. doi:10.22331/q-2025-03-25-1670. ISSN 2521-327X. https://quantum-journal.org/papers/q-2025-03-25-1670/

  65. Wimmel, Hermann (1992-05-26). Quantum Physics And Observed Reality: A Critical Interpretation Of Quantum Mechanics. World Scientific. p. 45. ISBN 978-981-4505-46-8. 978-981-4505-46-8

  66. Everett, Hugh; Wheeler, J. A.; DeWitt, B. S.; Cooper, L. N.; Van Vechten, D.; Graham, N. (1973). DeWitt, Bryce; Graham, R. Neill (eds.). The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton Series in Physics. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. p. v. ISBN 0-691-08131-X. 0-691-08131-X

  67. "Whether you can observe a thing or not depends on the theory which you use. It is the theory which decides what can be observed."—Albert Einstein to Werner Heisenberg, objecting to placing observables at the heart of the new quantum mechanics, during Heisenberg's 1926 lecture at Berlin; related by Heisenberg in 1968.[33] /wiki/Albert_Einstein

  68. Everett, Hugh; Wheeler, J. A.; DeWitt, B. S.; Cooper, L. N.; Van Vechten, D.; Graham, N. (1973). DeWitt, Bryce; Graham, R. Neill (eds.). The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton Series in Physics. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. p. v. ISBN 0-691-08131-X. 0-691-08131-X

  69. Deutsch, D. (1985). "Quantum theory as a universal physical theory". International Journal of Theoretical Physics. 24 (1): 1–41. Bibcode:1985IJTP...24....1D. doi:10.1007/BF00670071. S2CID 17530632. /wiki/David_Deutsch

  70. Vaidman, Lev (2018). Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qm-manyworlds/

  71. Wallace, David (2003). "Everettian Rationality: defending Deutsch's approach to probability in the Everett interpretation". Stud. Hist. Phil. Mod. Phys. 34 (3): 415–438. arXiv:quant-ph/0303050. Bibcode:2003SHPMP..34..415W. doi:10.1016/S1355-2198(03)00036-4. S2CID 1921913. /wiki/ArXiv_(identifier)

  72. Hugh Everett Theory of the Universal Wavefunction, Thesis, Princeton University, (1956, 1973), pp. 1–140. /wiki/Hugh_Everett

  73. Hugh Everett Theory of the Universal Wavefunction, Thesis, Princeton University, (1956, 1973), pp. 1–140. /wiki/Hugh_Everett

  74. Ballentine, L. E. (1973). "Can the statistical postulate of quantum theory be derived?—A critique of the many-universes interpretation". Foundations of Physics. 3 (2): 229–240. Bibcode:1973FoPh....3..229B. doi:10.1007/BF00708440. S2CID 121747282. /wiki/Bibcode_(identifier)

  75. Landsman, N. P. (2008). "The Born rule and its interpretation" (PDF). In Weinert, F.; Hentschel, K.; Greenberger, D.; Falkenburg, B. (eds.). Compendium of Quantum Physics. Springer. ISBN 978-3-540-70622-9. The conclusion seems to be that no generally accepted derivation of the Born rule has been given to date, but this does not imply that such a derivation is impossible in principle. 978-3-540-70622-9

  76. Kent, Adrian (2010). "One world versus many: The inadequacy of Everettian accounts of evolution, probability, and scientific confirmation". In Saunders, S.; Barrett, J.; Kent, A.; Wallace, D. (eds.). Many Worlds? Everett, Quantum Theory and Reality. Oxford University Press. arXiv:0905.0624. Bibcode:2009arXiv0905.0624K. /wiki/ArXiv_(identifier)

  77. Kent, Adrian (1990). "Against Many-Worlds Interpretations". International Journal of Modern Physics A. 5 (9): 1745–1762. arXiv:gr-qc/9703089. Bibcode:1990IJMPA...5.1745K. doi:10.1142/S0217751X90000805. S2CID 14523184. /wiki/ArXiv_(identifier)

  78. Everett, Hugh; Wheeler, J. A.; DeWitt, B. S.; Cooper, L. N.; Van Vechten, D.; Graham, N. (1973). DeWitt, Bryce; Graham, R. Neill (eds.). The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton Series in Physics. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. p. v. ISBN 0-691-08131-X. 0-691-08131-X

  79. Farhi, Edward; Goldstone, Jeffrey; Gutmann, Sam (1989). "How probability arises in quantum mechanics". Annals of Physics. 192 (2): 368–382. Bibcode:1989AnPhy.192..368F. doi:10.1016/0003-4916(89)90141-3. /wiki/Bibcode_(identifier)

  80. Benioff, Paul (October 1978). "A note on the Everett interpretation of quantum mechanics". Foundations of Physics. 8 (9–10): 709–720. Bibcode:1978FoPh....8..709B. doi:10.1007/BF00717501. ISSN 0015-9018. S2CID 123279967. /wiki/Paul_Benioff

  81. Caves, Carlton M.; Schack, Rüdiger (2005). "Properties of the frequency operator do not imply the quantum probability postulate". Annals of Physics. 315 (1): 123–146. arXiv:quant-ph/0409144. Bibcode:2005AnPhy.315..123C. doi:10.1016/j.aop.2004.09.009. S2CID 33263618. /wiki/Carlton_M._Caves

  82. Deutsch, David (1999). "Quantum Theory of Probability and Decisions". Proceedings of the Royal Society A: Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences. 455 (1988): 3129–3137. arXiv:quant-ph/9906015. Bibcode:1999RSPSA.455.3129D. doi:10.1098/rspa.1999.0443. S2CID 5217034. /wiki/ArXiv_(identifier)

  83. Wallace, David (2003). "Everettian Rationality: defending Deutsch's approach to probability in the Everett interpretation". Stud. Hist. Phil. Mod. Phys. 34 (3): 415–438. arXiv:quant-ph/0303050. Bibcode:2003SHPMP..34..415W. doi:10.1016/S1355-2198(03)00036-4. S2CID 1921913. /wiki/ArXiv_(identifier)

  84. Wallace, David (2002). "Quantum Probability and Decision Theory, Revisited". arXiv:quant-ph/0211104. /wiki/ArXiv_(identifier)

  85. Wallace, David (2003). "Quantum Probability from Subjective Likelihood: Improving on Deutsch's proof of the probability rule". arXiv:quant-ph/0312157. /wiki/ArXiv_(identifier)

  86. Wallace, David (2009). "A formal proof of the Born rule from decision-theoretic assumptions". arXiv:0906.2718 [quant-ph]. /wiki/ArXiv_(identifier)

  87. Saunders, Simon (2004). "Derivation of the Born rule from operational assumptions". Proc. R. Soc. Lond. A. 460 (2046): 1771–1788. arXiv:quant-ph/0211138. Bibcode:2004RSPSA.460.1771S. doi:10.1098/rspa.2003.1230. S2CID 1459183. /wiki/ArXiv_(identifier)

  88. Saunders, Simon (2004). "What is Probability?". Quo Vadis Quantum Mechanics?. The Frontiers Collection. pp. 209–238. arXiv:quant-ph/0412194. doi:10.1007/3-540-26669-0_12. ISBN 978-3-540-22188-3. S2CID 117218061. 978-3-540-22188-3

  89. Merali, Zeeya (2007-09-21). "Parallel universes make quantum sense". New Scientist. No. 2622. Retrieved 2013-11-22. (Summary only). https://www.newscientist.com/article/mg19526223.700-parallel-universes-make-quantum-sense.html

  90. "Perimeter Institute, Many worlds at 50 conference, September 21–24, 2007"."Videos". http://www.perimeterinstitute.ca/conferences/many-worlds-50

  91. Merali, Zeeya (2007-09-21). "Parallel universes make quantum sense". New Scientist. No. 2622. Retrieved 2013-11-22. (Summary only). https://www.newscientist.com/article/mg19526223.700-parallel-universes-make-quantum-sense.html

  92. Price, Huw (2010). "Decisions, Decisions, Decisions: Can Savage Salvage Everettian Probability?". In Saunders, S.; Barrett, J.; Kent, A.; Wallace, D. (eds.). Many Worlds? Everett, Quantum Theory and Reality. Oxford University Press. arXiv:0802.1390. /wiki/ArXiv_(identifier)

  93. Zurek, Wojciech H. (2005). "Probabilities from entanglement, Born's rule from envariance". Physical Review A. 71 (5): 052105. arXiv:quant-ph/0405161. Bibcode:2005PhRvA..71e2105Z. doi:10.1103/physreva.71.052105. S2CID 18210481. /wiki/Wojciech_H._Zurek

  94. Schlosshauer, M.; Fine, A. (2005). "On Zurek's derivation of the Born rule". Foundations of Physics. 35 (2): 197–213. arXiv:quant-ph/0312058. Bibcode:2005FoPh...35..197S. doi:10.1007/s10701-004-1941-6. S2CID 119100306. /wiki/ArXiv_(identifier)

  95. Vaidman, L. "Probability in the Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics." In: Ben-Menahem, Y., & Hemmo, M. (eds), The Probable and the Improbable: Understanding Probability in Physics, Essays in Memory of Itamar Pitowsky. Springer.

  96. Sebens, Charles T.; Carroll, Sean M. (2016). "Self-Locating Uncertainty and the Origin of Probability in Everettian Quantum Mechanics". The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. 69 (1): 25–74. arXiv:1405.7577. doi:10.1093/bjps/axw004. S2CID 53648469. /wiki/ArXiv_(identifier)

  97. Kent, Adrian (February 2015). "Does it Make Sense to Speak of Self-Locating Uncertainty in the Universal Wave Function? Remarks on Sebens and Carroll". Foundations of Physics. 45 (2): 211–217. arXiv:1408.1944. Bibcode:2015FoPh...45..211K. doi:10.1007/s10701-014-9862-5. ISSN 0015-9018. S2CID 118471198. /wiki/Adrian_Kent

  98. Vaidman, Lev (2020). "Derivations of the Born Rule". In Meir Hemmo; Orly Shenker (eds.). Quantum, Probability, Logic: Itamar Pitowsky's Work and Influence. Springer Nature Switzerland. PhilSci: 15943. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/15943

  99. Saunders, Simon (24 November 2021). "Branch-counting in the Everett interpretation of quantum mechanics". Proceedings of the Royal Society A. 477 (2255): 1–22. arXiv:2201.06087. Bibcode:2021RSPSA.47710600S. doi:10.1098/rspa.2021.0600. S2CID 244491576. /wiki/Simon_Saunders

  100. Skyrms, Brian (1976). "Possible Worlds, Physics and Metaphysics". Philosophical Studies. 30 (5): 323–332. doi:10.1007/BF00357930. S2CID 170852547. /wiki/Brian_Skyrms

  101. Ballentine, L. E. (1973). "Can the statistical postulate of quantum theory be derived?—A critique of the many-universes interpretation". Foundations of Physics. 3 (2): 229–240. Bibcode:1973FoPh....3..229B. doi:10.1007/BF00708440. S2CID 121747282. /wiki/Bibcode_(identifier)

  102. Saunders, Simon (2010). "Many Worlds? An Introduction". In Saunders, S.; Barrett, J.; Kent, A.; Wallace, D. (eds.). Many Worlds? Everett, Quantum Theory and Reality (PDF). Oxford University Press. /wiki/Simon_Saunders

  103. Gell-Mann, M.; Hartle, J. B. (1990). "Quantum mechanics in the light of quantum cosmology". In Zurek, W. H. (ed.). Complexity, Entropy, and the Physics of Information. Addison-Wesley. arXiv:1803.04605. /wiki/ArXiv_(identifier)

  104. Saunders, Simon (1993). "Decoherence, relative states, and evolutionary adaptation". Foundations of Physics. 23 (12): 1553–1585. Bibcode:1993FoPh...23.1553S. doi:10.1007/BF00732365. S2CID 119754481. /wiki/Bibcode_(identifier)

  105. Saunders, Simon (1995). "Time, quantum mechanics, and decoherence" (PDF). Synthese. 102 (2): 235–266. doi:10.1007/BF01089802. S2CID 14550985. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/463/1/part1.pdf

  106. Hartle, James B. (2011). "The quasiclassical realms of this quantum universe". Foundations of Physics. 41 (6): 982–1006. arXiv:0806.3776. Bibcode:2011FoPh...41..982H. doi:10.1007/s10701-010-9460-0. S2CID 118469123. /wiki/ArXiv_(identifier)

  107. Stapp, Henry (2002). "The basis problem in many-world theories" (PDF). Canadian Journal of Physics. 80 (9): 1043–1052. arXiv:quant-ph/0110148. Bibcode:2002CaJPh..80.1043S. doi:10.1139/p02-068. S2CID 18634782. http://www-physics.lbl.gov/~stapp/bp.PDF

  108. Wallace, David (2003). "Everett and structure". Studies in History and Philosophy of Science. 34 (1): 87–105. arXiv:quant-ph/0107144. Bibcode:2003SHPMP..34...87W. doi:10.1016/S1355-2198(02)00085-0. S2CID 15222560. /wiki/ArXiv_(identifier)

  109. Wallace, David (2010). "Decoherence and Ontology, or: How I Learned To Stop Worrying And Love FAPP". In Saunders, S.; Barrett, J.; Kent, A.; Wallace, D. (eds.). Many Worlds? Everett, Quantum Theory and Reality. Oxford University Press. arXiv:1111.2189. /wiki/ArXiv_(identifier)

  110. Brown, Harvey R; Wallace, David (2005). "Solving the measurement problem: de Broglie–Bohm loses out to Everett" (PDF). Foundations of Physics. 35 (4): 517–540. arXiv:quant-ph/0403094. Bibcode:2005FoPh...35..517B. doi:10.1007/s10701-004-2009-3. S2CID 412240. /wiki/Harvey_Brown_(philosopher)

  111. Kent, Adrian (2010). "One world versus many: The inadequacy of Everettian accounts of evolution, probability, and scientific confirmation". In Saunders, S.; Barrett, J.; Kent, A.; Wallace, D. (eds.). Many Worlds? Everett, Quantum Theory and Reality. Oxford University Press. arXiv:0905.0624. Bibcode:2009arXiv0905.0624K. /wiki/ArXiv_(identifier)

  112. Zurek, Wojciech H. (2005). "Probabilities from entanglement, Born's rule from envariance". Physical Review A. 71 (5): 052105. arXiv:quant-ph/0405161. Bibcode:2005PhRvA..71e2105Z. doi:10.1103/physreva.71.052105. S2CID 18210481. /wiki/Wojciech_H._Zurek

  113. Baker, David J. (2007). "Measurement outcomes and probability in Everettian quantum mechanics" (PDF). Studies in History and Philosophy of Science. 38 (1): 153–169. Bibcode:2007SHPMP..38..153B. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2006.05.003. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/2717/1/OutcomeProbEverett.pdf

  114. Wallace, David (2012). The Emergent Multiverse: Quantum Theory According to the Everett Interpretation. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-954696-1. 978-0-19-954696-1

  115. Everett, Hugh; Wheeler, J. A.; DeWitt, B. S.; Cooper, L. N.; Van Vechten, D.; Graham, N. (1973). DeWitt, Bryce; Graham, R. Neill (eds.). The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton Series in Physics. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. p. v. ISBN 0-691-08131-X. 0-691-08131-X

  116. Wheeler, John Archibald (2000). Geons, Black Holes and Quantum Foam. W. W. Norton & Company. pp. 268–270. ISBN 0-393-31991-1. 0-393-31991-1

  117. Everett, Hugh; Wheeler, J. A.; DeWitt, B. S.; Cooper, L. N.; Van Vechten, D.; Graham, N. (1973). DeWitt, Bryce; Graham, R. Neill (eds.). The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton Series in Physics. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. p. v. ISBN 0-691-08131-X. 0-691-08131-X

  118. Osnaghi, Stefano; Freitas, Fabio; Olival Freire, Jr (2009). "The Origin of the Everettian Heresy". Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 40 (2): 97–123. Bibcode:2009SHPMP..40...97O. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.397.3933. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2008.10.002. /wiki/Olival_Freire,_Jr.

  119. Deutsch, David (2010). "Apart from Universes". In S. Saunders; J. Barrett; A. Kent; D. Wallace (eds.). Many Worlds? Everett, Quantum Theory and Reality. Oxford University Press. /wiki/David_Deutsch

  120. Schrödinger, Erwin (1996). Bitbol, Michel (ed.). The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics: Dublin Seminars (1949–1955) and other unpublished essays. OxBow Press. /wiki/Michel_Bitbol

  121. Barrett, Jeffrey A. (1999). The Quantum Mechanics of Minds and Worlds. Oxford University Press. pp. 62–63. ISBN 9780191583254. 9780191583254

  122. Bitbol, Michel (1996). Schrödinger's Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands. ISBN 978-94-009-1772-9. OCLC 851376153. 978-94-009-1772-9

  123. Cooper, Leon N.; Van Vechten, Deborah (1969-12-01). "On the Interpretation of Measurement within the Quantum Theory". American Journal of Physics. 37 (12): 1212–1220. doi:10.1119/1.1975279. ISSN 0002-9505. https://pubs.aip.org/ajp/article/37/12/1212/1048185/On-the-Interpretation-of-Measurement-within-the

  124. Camilleri, Kristian (2009). "A history of entanglement: Decoherence and the interpretation problem". Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 40 (4): 290–302. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2009.09.003. https://linkinghub.elsevier.com/retrieve/pii/S1355219809000562

  125. Byrne, Peter (2010). The Many Worlds of Hugh Everett III: Multiple Universes, Mutual Assured Destruction, and the Meltdown of a Nuclear Family. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-955227-6. 978-0-19-955227-6

  126. Aldhous, Peter (2007-11-24). "Parallel lives can never touch". New Scientist. No. 2631. Retrieved 2007-11-21. https://www.newscientist.com/article/mg19626311.800-interview-parallel-lives-can-never-touch.html

  127. Osnaghi, Stefano; Freitas, Fabio; Olival Freire, Jr (2009). "The Origin of the Everettian Heresy". Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 40 (2): 97–123. Bibcode:2009SHPMP..40...97O. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.397.3933. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2008.10.002. /wiki/Olival_Freire,_Jr.

  128. Everett recounted his meeting with Bohr as "that was a hell... doomed from the beginning". Léon Rosenfeld, a close collaborator of Bohr, said "With regard to Everett neither I nor even Niels Bohr could have any patience with him, when he visited us in Copenhagen more than 12 years ago in order to sell the hopelessly wrong ideas he had been encouraged, most unwisely, by Wheeler to develop. He was undescribably[sic] stupid and could not understand the simplest things in quantum mechanics."[14]: 113 /wiki/L%C3%A9on_Rosenfeld

  129. John Gribbin, In Search of Schrödinger's Cat, ISBN 978-0552125550, p. 246. /wiki/John_Gribbin

  130. David Deutsch, The Fabric of Reality: The Science of Parallel Universes And Its Implications, Penguin Books (1998), ISBN 0-14-027541-X. /wiki/David_Deutsch

  131. Deutsch, David (1985). "Quantum theory, the Church–Turing principle and the universal quantum computer". Proceedings of the Royal Society of London A. 400 (1818): 97–117. Bibcode:1985RSPSA.400...97D. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.144.7936. doi:10.1098/rspa.1985.0070. S2CID 1438116. /wiki/David_Deutsch

  132. Paul C.W. Davies, J. R. Brown, The Ghost in the Atom (1986) ISBN 0-521-31316-3, pp. 34–38: "The Many-Universes Interpretation", pp. 83–105 for David Deutsch's test of MWI and reversible quantum memories. /wiki/Paul_C.W._Davies

  133. Ladyman, James; Ross, Don (2007). Every Thing Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalized. Clarendon Press. pp. 179–183. ISBN 978-0-19-927619-6. 978-0-19-927619-6

  134. Bunge, M. (2012). "Parallel Universes? Digital Physics?". Evaluating Philosophies. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science. Vol. 295. New York: Springer. pp. 152–153. doi:10.1007/978-94-007-4408-0. ISBN 978-94-007-4407-3. 978-94-007-4407-3

  135. Ellis, G.; Silk, J. (2014). "Scientific method: Defend the integrity of physics". Nature. 516 (7531): 321–323. Bibcode:2014Natur.516..321E. doi:10.1038/516321a. PMID 25519115. https://doi.org/10.1038%2F516321a

  136. Stenger, V. J. (1995). The Unconscious Quantum: Metaphysics in Modern Physics and Cosmology. Prometheus Books. ISBN 978-1-57392-022-3. LCCN lc95032599. 978-1-57392-022-3

  137. "Gell-Mann and Hartle, along with a score of others, have been working to develop a more palatable interpretation of quantum mechanics that is free of the problems that plague all the interpretations we have considered so far. This new interpretation is called, in its various incarnations, post-Everett quantum mechanics, alternate histories, consistent histories, or decoherent histories. I will not be overly concerned with the detailed differences between these characterizations and will use the terms more or less interchangeably."[82]: 176

  138. Penrose, Roger (August 1991). "Roger Penrose Looks Beyond the Classic-Quantum Dichotomy". Sciencewatch. Archived from the original on 2007-10-23. Retrieved 2007-10-21. /wiki/Roger_Penrose

  139. Ball, Philip (2015-02-17). "Too many worlds". Aeon.co. Retrieved 2021-09-23. /wiki/Philip_Ball

  140. "If an Electron Can Be in Two Places at Once, Why Can't You?". Discover Magazine. https://www.discovermagazine.com/the-sciences/if-an-electron-can-be-in-two-places-at-once-why-cant-you

  141. Ball, Philip (2015-02-17). "Too many worlds". Aeon.co. Retrieved 2021-09-23. /wiki/Philip_Ball

  142. Ball, Philip (2015-02-17). "Too many worlds". Aeon.co. Retrieved 2021-09-23. /wiki/Philip_Ball

  143. Melinda, Baldwin (2017-07-11). "Q&A: Gerard 't Hooft on the future of quantum mechanics". Physics Today. No. 7. doi:10.1063/PT.6.4.20170711a. https://physicstoday.scitation.org/do/10.1063/PT.6.4.20170711a/abs/

  144. Peres, Asher (1995). Quantum Theory: Concepts and Methods. Kluwer Academic Publishers. p. 374. ISBN 0-7923-2549-4. 0-7923-2549-4

  145. Tipler, Frank (1994). The Physics of Immortality:Modern Cosmology, God and the Resurrection of the Dead. pp. 170–171. In the "yes" column were Stephen Hawking, Richard Feynman, and Murray Gell-Mann /wiki/Frank_J._Tipler

  146. "Max Tegmark on many-worlds (contains MWI poll)". http://space.mit.edu/home/tegmark/quantum.html

  147. Caroll, Sean (1 April 2004). "Preposterous Universe". Archived from the original on 8 September 2004. https://web.archive.org/web/20040908014703/http://preposterousuniverse.blogspot.com/2004_04_01_preposterousuniverse_archive.html#108087902367974365

  148. Nielsen, Michael (3 April 2004). "Michael Nielsen: The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics". Archived from the original on 20 May 2004. https://web.archive.org/web/20040520222807/http://www.qinfo.org/people/nielsen/blog/archive/000060.html

  149. Survey Results Archived 2010-11-04 at the Wayback Machine http://www.iqc.ca/~qipcourse/interpret/survey.html

  150. Schlosshauer, Maximilian; Kofler, Johannes; Zeilinger, Anton (2013). "A Snapshot of Foundational Attitudes Toward Quantum Mechanics". Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 44 (3): 222–230. arXiv:1301.1069. Bibcode:2013SHPMP..44..222S. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2013.04.004. S2CID 55537196. /wiki/ArXiv_(identifier)

  151. Schlosshauer, Maximilian; Kofler, Johannes; Zeilinger, Anton (2013). "A Snapshot of Foundational Attitudes Toward Quantum Mechanics". Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 44 (3): 222–230. arXiv:1301.1069. Bibcode:2013SHPMP..44..222S. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2013.04.004. S2CID 55537196. /wiki/ArXiv_(identifier)

  152. DeWitt, Bryce S. (1970). "Quantum mechanics and reality". Physics Today. 23 (9): 30–35. Bibcode:1970PhT....23i..30D. doi:10.1063/1.3022331. See also Ballentine, Leslie E.; Pearle, Philip; Walker, Evan Harris; Sachs, Mendel; Koga, Toyoki; Gerver, Joseph; DeWitt, Bryce (1971). "Quantum-mechanics debate". Physics Today. 24 (4): 36–44. Bibcode:1971PhT....24d..36.. doi:10.1063/1.3022676. https://doi.org/10.1063%2F1.3022331

  153. Tegmark, Max. "The Universes of Max Tegmark". space.mit.edu. Retrieved 2023-08-26. https://space.mit.edu/home/tegmark/crazy.html

  154. David Deutsch. Beginning of Infinity, Penguin Books (2011), ISBN 978-0-7139-9274-8, p. 294. /wiki/ISBN_(identifier)

  155. John Gribbin, Six Impossible Things, Icon Books Limited (2021), ISBN 978-1-7857-8734-8. /wiki/John_Gribbin

  156. Ladyman, James; Ross, Don (2007). Every Thing Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalized. Clarendon Press. pp. 179–183. ISBN 978-0-19-927619-6. 978-0-19-927619-6

  157. Carroll, Sean (2019-09-10). Something Deeply Hidden: Quantum Worlds and the Emergence of Spacetime. Penguin. ISBN 978-1-5247-4302-4. 978-1-5247-4302-4

  158. Tegmark, Max (November 1998). "Quantum immortality". Retrieved 25 October 2010. http://space.mit.edu/home/tegmark/quantum.html#immortality

  159. Wallace, David (2012). The Emergent Multiverse: Quantum Theory According to the Everett Interpretation. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-954696-1. 978-0-19-954696-1

  160. Vaidman, Lev (2018). Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qm-manyworlds/

  161. Carroll, Sean (2019-09-10). Something Deeply Hidden: Quantum Worlds and the Emergence of Spacetime. Penguin. ISBN 978-1-5247-4302-4. 978-1-5247-4302-4

  162. Deutsch, David (2011). "The Beginning". The Beginning of Infinity. Penguin Group.